Linguistic Discovery
Dartmouth College

Volume 12 Issue 2 (2014)        DOI:10.1349/PS1.1537-0852.A.443

Note: Linguistic Discovery uses Unicode characters to represent phonetic symbols. Please see Optimizing Display for requirements to accurately reproduce this page.

Emai’s Variable Coding of Adjuncts

Ronald P. Schaefer and Francis O. Egbokhare

Southern Illinois University Edwardsville and University of Ibadan

This paper examines the morphosyntactic character of clauses containing adjuncts in Emai (Edoid and West Benue Congo). In clauses differing as to discourse function, adjunct coding is variable. Some adjunct types are consistently structured as either head of a phrase or complement in a phrase headed by a verb. Other adjuncts are coded more variably. In canonical declarative clauses, they appear in postverbal position unmarked by a verb, but in one or more noncanonical clause types, their clause requires a verb otherwise latent. Resulting patterns are assessed from a perspective in Croft (2001), where adjuncts are relations with their matrix clause as argument.

1. Introduction[1]

The adjunct/argument distinction is widely recognized in language description and explanation. It is most often associated with a syntactic criterion; nonetheless, the semantic nature of adjuncts and arguments has drawn some attention (Matthews 1981, 2007, Croft 2001). For the languages of sub-Saharan Africa, adjunct and argument have received minimal scrutiny. Watters (2000) notes that adjuncts (X) generally follow objects (O) in SVOX languages, while in SOV languages they either precede V (SXOV) or follow V (SOVX).

For this paper, we explore adjunct structures in Emai, a West Benue Congo language within southern Nigeria’s Edoid group (Elugbe 1989, Williamson and Blench 2000). Typologically, Emai is relatively strict SVO with lexical and grammatical tone but little inflectional morphology and few prepositions (Schaefer and Egbokhare 1999, 2007, to appear). Word order is pervasive as a marker of grammatical relations. Regarding clause structure, Emai is characterized by simple predicates as well as complex predicates consisting of verbs in series, verbs in construction with postverbal particles, and verbs in series with verbs and postverbal particles (Schaefer and Egbokhare 2010). In addition, Emai shows an extensive array of preverbs (Schaefer and Egbokhare 2000), many of them adverb like, that affect interpretation of clausal event (che ‘again,’ ya ‘almost,’ duu ‘for no reason,’ kakégbe ‘perseveringly,’ kpao ‘initially’) or a core participant (zemi ‘very many,’ gba ‘together’).[2]

2. Adjunct Character

Croft (2001) reviews a number of criteria proposed to distinguish adjuncts from arguments. The classic syntactic criterion holds that adjunct constituents are optional while arguments are obligatory. This seems relatively straightforward. In (1a-b), an adjunct (e.g. in the park) is peripheral to its associated verb, since it can be omitted without consequence to grammaticalness. In contrast, arguments (George, the dog) are obligatory relative to their predicate; argument omission results in ungrammaticality (1a-c).

(1a) George chased the dog in the park.

(1b) George chased the dog.

(1c) *George chased in the park.

Questions arising from Croft’s analysis and illustration are no doubt multiple. Two, however, concern us. One is whether the distributional potential that characterizes locative (i.e. in the park), applies equally to other adjunct types, for instance those expressing temporality (for the afternoon in 2a) or manner (clumsily in 2b).

(2a) George chased the dog for the afternoon.

(2b) George chased the dog clumsily.

A second focuses on whether all adjunct types lead to consistent morphosyntactic expression across canonical and noncanonical clause types.[3]

Directing these questions toward Emai, we find that adjuncts in clause types differing as to discourse function attract nonuniform coding. Some adjunct types across canonical and noncanonical clauses occur as either head of a phrase or as complement in a phrase headed by a verb. Other adjuncts are coded more variably. In canonical declarative clauses, they appear in postverbal position unmarked by a verb, but in one or more noncanonical clause types, e.g. imperative, interrogative or contrastive focus, their clause requires a verb otherwise latent. As an initial sample of this variability, we present Table 1. It reveals that outside of manner, which is consistently unmarked by a verb, and reason, which is consistently verb marked (by re), adjuncts with a locative or temporal character require, in addition to a main verb, a latent verb such as re or za.[4]

 

DECL

IMP

INTER

CF

MANNER

verb AD

verb AD

   
         

TEMPORAL DEIXIS

verb AD

verb AD

re verb

AD verb

         

TEMPORAL BOUND

verb AD

re AD verb

   
         

TEMPORAL QUANTITY

verb AD

re AD verb

re verb

 
         
         

LOCATIVE

verb AD

verb AD

za verb

AD za verb

         

REASON

re AD verb

re AD verb

 

AD re verb

         

Table 1: Emai adjunct (AD) occurrence with main verb and latent verb (za or re) across clauses that are canonical, i.e. declarative (DECL), and noncanonical, i.e. imperative (IMP), interrogative (INTER) and contrastive focus (CF).

3. Emai Adjuncts and Arguments

Argument types in Emai exhibit rather consistent distributional behavior compared to the more variable nature of adjuncts. A direct object argument (óràn ‘wood’), whose grammatical relation is morphologically unmarked but syntactically indicated by word order, follows a transitive verb such as hian ‘cut’ (3a). Verbs like hian also occur in series with a transitive verb such as re ‘take,’ which precedes its obligatory direct object argument (ópìà ‘cutlass,’ 3b-c). Both arguments relate to an overall event of cutting.

(3a)

òjè

híán

óràn. /

*òjè

híán.

 

Oje

PRP.cut

wood

Oje

PRP.cut

 

‘Oje cut wood. / Oje cut.’

(3b)

òjè

ré

ópìà

híán

óràn.

 

Oje

PRP.take

cutlass

cut

wood

 

‘Oje used a cutlass to cut wood.’

(3c)

*òjè

ré

híán

óràn.

 

Oje

PRP.take

cut

wood

 

‘Oje cut wood.’

As well, intransitive verbs in series such as za ‘be located’ and se ‘move up to, as far as, reach, extend to’ precede their obligatory arguments marked by locative preposition vbi (4a-b).

(4a)

òjè

vbí

áfúzé'

shán

sé

vbì

òkè.

 

Oje

PRP.be.located

LOC

Afuze

walk

move.up.to

LOC

Oke

 

‘Oje walked from Afuze to Oke.’

(4b)

*òjè

shàn

sé

vbì

òkè.

 

Oje

PRP.be.located

walk

move.up.to

LOC

Oke

‘Oje walked to Oke.’

Emai adjunct types display some distributional consistency across clauses as well. In canonical declaratives they prototypically occupy postpredicate position following an intransitive verb or direct object of a transitive verb. As constituents adjuncts occur either unmarked or marked by preposition vbi. Unmarked are temporal deictic adjuncts (òdè ‘yesterday’ 5a) and temporal quantity adjunct phrases (íkpédè èéà ‘for three days’ 5b). Marked by vbi are temporal ordinal adjunct phrases (úkpédéózèéà ‘on the third day’ 5c) and locative adjuncts (ímè ‘farm’ 5d).

(5a)

ójé

híán'

órán

òdè.

 

Oje

PAP.cut

wood

yesterday

 

‘Oje cut wood yesterday.’

(5b)

ójé

híán'

órán

íkpédè

èéà.

 

Oje

PAP.cut

wood

days

three

 

‘Oje cut wood for three days.’

(5c)

ójé

híán'

órán

vbí

úkpédé

ózèéà.

 

Oje

PAP.cut

wood

LOC

day

R

third

 

‘Oje cut wood on the third day.’

(5d)

ójé

híán'

órán

vbí

ímè.

 

Oje

PAP.cut

wood

LOC

farm

 

‘Oje cut wood on the farm.’

A distinguishing feature of adjuncts, as opposed to arguments, is their tonal impact on a preceding constituent. Relative to a preceding verb argument (óràn), Emai adjuncts activate high tone spread starting at argument right edge, as in órán òdè (5a) versus óràn (3a). Nonadverb constituents following a verb argument do not activate high tone spread however. In (3b), where verb hian follows argument ópìà, high tone spread is not activated. Verbs in series thus do not trigger high tone spread. In addition, postverbal particles that follow a direct object argument do not activate high tone spread (6a-c), as shown by right edge low tone of úì ‘rope’ preceding Terminative lee ‘already, finish,’ Change of Location o or Applicative li.

(6a)

òjè

híán

ó

úì

léé.

 

Oje

PRP.cut

the

rope

TERM

 

‘Oje finished cutting the rope / already cut the rope.’

(6b)

òjè

híán

ó

úì

ó

vbì

èvá.

 

Oje

PRP.cut

the

rope

CL

LOC

two

 

‘Oje cut the rope into two.’

(6c)

òjè

híán

ó

úì

òhí.

 

Oje

PRP.cut

the

rope

APP

Ohi

 

‘Oje cut the rope for Ohi.’

An important feature of nondeclarative clauses containing Emai adjuncts pertains to their potential for variable coding. In information question clauses, temporal deictic adjuncts represented by òdè ‘yesterday,’ for example, correspond to an interrogative proform (éghè ‘when’). Their predicate phrase requires the verb re ‘take’ as the initial verb in series (7), despite the fact that re never occurs in the corresponding declarative clause, cf. (5a).[5]

(7)

éghè

ójé

ré'

híán

ó

óràn?

 

time

Oje

PAP.take

cut

the

wood

 

‘When did Oje cut the wood?’

 

òdè.

 

yesterday

 

‘Yesterday.’

A similar condition holds for a vbi marked adjunct of place. In transitive declaratives, where a locative adjunct follows a verb and its direct object, place marking is signaled by preposition vbi (5d). In information questions, where the locative corresponds to a fronted interrogative proform, the verb za ‘be located’ occurs in the matrix clause and precedes other verbs in series. Thus in declarative (8a), ímè ‘farm’ appears in postverbal position preceded by preposition vbi; no za marks it. However, when adjunct ímè corresponds to an interrogative proform (ébé' ‘where’), za is obligatory in the predicate phrase (8b).

(8a)

ójé

híán'

órán

vbí

ímè.

 

Oje

PAP.cut

wood

LOC

farm

 

‘Oje cut wood on the farm.’

(8b)

ébé'

ójé

zá'

híán

óràn?

 

where

Oje

PAP.be.located

cut

wood

 

‘Where did Oje cut wood?’

 

ímè.

 

farm

 

‘On the farm.’

Fronting of a locative adjunct in a contrastive focus clause leads to similar marking by za. When ímè occurs in focus position and precedes positive focus (PF) morpheme li, za is required in the matrix clause as the initial verb in series.

(9)

ímè

ójé

zá'

híán

óràn.

 

farm

PF

Oje

PAP.be.located

cut

wood

 

‘It was on a farm that Oje cut wood.’

In contrast, locative arguments of a verb do not give rise to za. As an argument of verb o ‘enter’ in declarative clauses, ímè in postverbal position follows preposition vbi.

(10)

òjè

ó

vbí

ímè.

 

Oje

PRP.enter

LOC

farm

 

‘Oje entered the farm.’

In information question clauses, where ímè corresponds to fronted interrogative proform ébé' ‘where,’ za is disallowed (11a-b). As well, occurrence of ímè in contrastive focus position does not lead to a matrix clause predicate phrase with za as a verb in series (11c).

(11a)

ébé'

ójé

ó'-ì?

 

where

Oje

PAP.enter-F

 

‘Where did Oje enter?’

(11b)

*ébé'

ójé

zá'

ó?

 

where

Oje

PAP.be.located

enter

 

‘Where did Oje enter?’

(11c)

ímè

mè

ójé

ó'-ì.

 

farm

my

PF

Oje

PAP.enter-F

 

‘It was my farm that Oje entered.’

It is likewise the case for vbi marked locative arguments (e.g. ùdékèn ‘wall’) with transitive verbs (e.g. fi ‘hit,’ 12a). Neither information question clauses (12b) nor negative contrastive focus clauses (12c) with such verbs lead to verb za in series.

(12a)

òjè

úkpórán

vbì

ùdékèn.

 

Oje

PRP.hit

stick

LOC

wall

 

‘Oje hit a stick on the wall.’

(12b)

ébé'

ójé

fí'

úkpóràn?

 

where

Oje

PAP.hit

stick

 

‘Where did Oje hit the stick?’

(12c)

ùdékèn

ójé

fí'

úkpóràn.

 

wall

NF

Oje

PAP.hit

stick

 

‘It wasn’t on a wall that Oje hit the stick.’

This brief overview of Emai locative and temporal forms reveals adjuncts in nondeclarative clauses scaffolded by a latent verb. Scaffold structures framed by a latent verb in series also affect adjuncts of temporal quantity. In declarative clauses íkpédè èéà ‘for three days,’ for instance, is postverbal and unmarked by a preposition (13a). In information question clauses (13b), where the temporal quantity constituent corresponds to a fronted interrogative proform (íkpédé ékà ‘how many days’), the verb re ‘take’ is obligatory and precedes other verbs in series.

(13a)

ójé

híán'

órán

íkpédè

èéà.

 

Oje

PAP.cut

wood

days

three

 

‘Oje cut wood for three days.’

(13b)

íkpédé

ékà

ójé

ré'

híán

óràn?

 

day

quantity

Oje

PAP.take

cut

wood

 

‘For how many days did Oje cut wood?’

 

íkpédè

èéà.

 

days

three

 

‘For three days.’

Imperative clauses with adjunct íkpédè èéà grammatically mandate re as well; re must occur in the matrix clause and in a position preceding other verbs in series (14a-b). Temporal quantity adjuncts, though, are not found in contrastive focus clauses.

(14a)

rè

íkpédè

èéà

híán

óràn.

 

take

days

three

cut

wood

 

‘Take three days to cut wood. / Cut wood for three days.’

(14b)

*hìàn

órán

íkpédè

èéà.

 

cut

wood

days

three

 

‘Cut wood for three days.’

Another adverbial adjunct type utilizing latent verb re expresses temporal bounding for an event. In declarative clauses, ékéín íkpédè èéà ‘within three days’ is marked by preposition vbi (15a) and occupies postpredicate position. In corresponding imperatives (15b), re is obligatory with ékéín íkpédè èéà as complement; the resulting re ékéín íkpédè èéà constituent precedes other verbs in series. Temporal bounding adjuncts articulate neither information question nor contrastive focus clauses.

(15a)

ó

ómó

híán'

ó

óràn

léé

vbí

ékéín

íkpédè

èéà.

 

the

man

PAP.cut

the

wood

TEMP

LOC

inside

days

three

 

‘The man had finished cutting the wood within three days.’

(15b)

rè

ékéín

íkpédè

èéà

híán

ó

óràn

léé.

 

take

inside

days

three

cut

the

wood

TEMP

 

‘Finish cutting the wood within three days.’

Not all adjuncts with temporal significance require latent re. In fact, some evince no latent verb as scaffold. Adjuncts expressing temporal ordinal relations (e.g. úkpédéózèéà ‘on the third day’), for instance, appear in postpredicate position marked by preposition vbi (16a). Nonetheless without latent re, they retain postpredicate position in imperative clauses (16b) and in contrastive focus clauses they occupy focus position (16c).[6]

(16a)

ó

ómó

híán'

ó

órán

vbí

úkpédé

ózèéà.

 

the

man

PAP.cut

the

wood

LOC

day

R

third

 

‘The man cut the wood on the third day.’

(16b)

hìàn

ó

órán

vbí

úkpédé

ózèéà.

 

cut

the

wood

LOC

day

R

third

 

‘Cut the wood on the third day.’

(16c)

úkpédé

ózèéà

ó

ómó

híán'

ó

óràn.

 

day

R

third

PF

the

man

PAP.cut

ó

wood

 

‘It was on the third day that the man cut the wood.’

Adjuncts expressing a temporal frequency relation (e.g. ìsèvá ‘twice’) also occur in postpredicate position (17a), although not as a constituent marked by preposition vbi. Without re or any other latent verb in the matrix clause, temporal frequency adjuncts retain postpredicate position in imperative clauses (17b), correspond in information questions to an interrogative pronoun (ísékà ‘how often’ in 17c) and occupy contrastive focus position (17d).

(17a)

ó

ómó

é'

ó

émáé

ìsèvá.

 

the

man

PAP.eat

the

food

twice

 

‘The man ate the food twice.’

(17b)

è

ó

émáé

ìsòkpá.

 

cut

the

wood

once

 

‘Eat the food at once.’

(17c)

ísékà

ó

ómó

é'

ó

émàè?

 

how.often

the

man

PAP.eat

the

food

 

‘How often did the man eat the food?’

 

ìsèvá.

 

twice

 

‘Twice.’

(17d)

ìsèvá

ó

ómó

é'

ó

émàè.

 

twice

PF

the

man

PAP.eat

the

food

 

‘It was twice that the man ate the food.’

In stark contrast to these last two temporal types, adjuncts expressing reason exhibit a more consistent verb scaffold pattern. Adjunct reason constituents (e.g. òó ísì òjè ‘because of Oje’) do not occur in postpredicate position in declarative clauses (18a). Instead, as complement they immediately follow verb re as the initial verb phrase in series in declaratives (18b), in imperatives (18c), and when they occupy contrastive focus position (18d), re is retained as the initial verb in series.[7]

(18a)

*ó

ómó

gbé'

ófé

òó

ísì

òjè.

 

the

man

PAP.kill

rat

cause

ASS

Oje

 

‘The man killed rats because of Oje.’

(18b)

ó

ómó

ré'

òó

ísì

òjè

gbé

ófè.

 

the

man

PAP.take

cause

ASS

Oje

kill

rat

 

‘The man killed rats because of Oje.’

(18c)

rè

òó

ísì

òjè

é

ó

émàè.

 

take

cause

ASS

Oje

eat

the

food

 

‘Use Oje as the reason for eating the food.’

(18d)

òó

ísì

òjè

ó

ómó

ré'

é

ó

émàè

léé.

 

cause

ASS

Oje

PF

the

man

PAP.take

eat

the

food

TEMP

 

‘It was because of Oje the man finished eating the food.’

Differing from reason adjuncts and exhibiting a distinct placement for their latent verb compared to temporal and locative types are adjuncts conveying aspectual and temporal extent. Adjuncts of aspectual extent (gbègbéí ‘completely’) occur in postpredicate position in declarative (19a) and imperative (19b) clauses. In information questions, where adjuncts of aspectual extent correspond to interrogative proform (ébé' ‘how’) and an accompanying manner (MAN) preverb i,[8] their matrix clause requires the postpredicate verb se ‘extend to, reach’ as the final verb in series (19c). Aspectual extent adjuncts fail to occupy contrastive focus position.

(19a)

ójé

ánmé'

óí

étò

á

gbègbéí.

 

Oje

PAP.scrape

her

hair

CS

completely

 

‘Oje scraped off her hair completely.’

(19b)

ànmè

óí

étò

á

gbègbéí.

 

scrape

her

hair

CS

completely

 

‘Scrape off her hair completely.’

(19c)

ébé'

ójé

í'

ánmé

óí

étò

sé?

 

how

Oje

PAP.MAN

scrape

her

hair

extend.to

 

‘To what extent did Oje scrape her hair?’

 

ó

ì

ànmè

óí

étó

á

gbègbéí.

 

he

NEG

scrape

her

hair

CS

completely

 

‘He did not scrape off her hair at all.’

Other aspectual extent adjuncts include jáún ‘completely, crisply’ (20a-b) and sésésé ‘completely, neatly’ (21a-b). In interrogative clauses they, too, give rise to latent verb se.

(20a)

ó

ógó

tóó'

á

jáún.

 

the

bush

PAP.burn

CS

crisply

 

‘The bush burned to a crisp.’

(20b)

ébé'

ó

ógó

í'

tòò

sé?

 

how

the

bush

PAP.MAN

burn

extend.to

 

‘To what extent did the bush burn?’

 

ó

tóó'

á

jáún.

 

the

PAP.burn

CS

crisply

 

‘It burned to a crisp.’

(21a)

ó

ótóí

fúán-í'

sésésé.

 

the

ground

PAP.be.clean-F

completely

 

‘The ground was absolutely clean.’

(21b)

ébé'

ó

ótóí

í'

fùàn

sé?

 

how

the

ground

PAP.MAN

be.clean

extend.to

 

‘To what extent was the ground clean?’

 

ó

fúán-í'

sésésé.

 

it

PAP.be.clean-F

completely

 

‘It was absolutely clean.’

Another adjunct type, temporal extent (títítí ‘long time’), occurs in postpredicate position in declarative (22a) clauses. In information questions, where adjuncts of temporal extent correspond to interrogative proform ébé' ‘how’ and its manner preverb i, their matrix clause requires not only the extent verb se in series but also the temporal verb tee ‘be long’ (22b). Temporal extent adjuncts do not appear in imperative clauses or occupy contrastive focus position.[9]

(22a)

ó

ómó

múzán-í'

títítí.

 

the

man

PAP.wait-F

long.time

 

‘The man waited for a long time.

(22b)

ébé'

ó

ómó

í'

mùzàn

téé

sè?

 

how

the

man

PAP.MAN

wait

be.long

extend.to

 

‘How long did the man wait?’

 

 

ó

múzán-í'

títítí.

 

the

PAP.wait-F

long.time

 

‘He waited for a long time.’

A distinct and final pattern characterizes adjuncts of manner. They reveal no evidence of a latent verb. Manner adjuncts (kóíkóí ‘in a gulping fashion’) occur in postpredicate position regardless of whether their clause is declarative (23a) or imperative (23b). When manner adjuncts in information questions correspond to interrogative proform (ébé' ‘how’) and manner preverb i (23c), their matrix clause fails to show a latent verb like se, re or za. Manner adjuncts of this type do not occupy contrastive focus position.

(23a)

ó

ómò

ò

ó

è

ó

émáé

kóíkóí.

 

the

man

SC

C

eat

the

food

gulpingly

 

‘The man is gulping the food / eating the food in a gulping fashion.’

(23b)

è

ó

émáé

kóíkóí.

 

eat

eat

food

gulpingly

 

‘Gulp the food. / Eat the food in a gulping fashion.’

(23c)

ébé'

ó

ómó

ó

ò

í

è

émàè?

 

how

the

man

SC

H

MAN

eat

food

 

‘How does the man eat food?’

 

ó

ò

è

óí

kóíkóí.

 

he

H

eat

it

gulpingly

 

‘He eats it in a gulping fashion. / He gulps it.’

4. Discussion

In the preceding section we called attention to Emai’s latent verb coding patterns for some clause structures that incorporate adjuncts. For several adjunct types (locative, temporal bounded, deixis and quantity as well as aspectual and temporal extent), one or more of their noncanonical clauses, i.e. imperative, interrogative or contrastive focus, were coded with a latent verb, whereas their canonical declarative clause was not. Moreover, coding was not uniform across adjunct types, either by latent verb form (re, za, se, tee) or position (pre- versus post-matrix predicate). Still other adjunct types revealed either no latent verb (manner, temporal frequency and temporal ordinal) or consistently required a preceding verb (reason). As a summary of Emai adjunct behavior and its accompanying clausal coding we present Table 2.

 

DECL

IMP

INTER

CF

R-Q

MANNER

verb AD

verb AD

ébé' i verb

 

in situ

           

A EXTENT

verb AD

verb AD

ébé' i verb se

 

in situ

T EXTENT

verb AD

 

ébé' i verb tee se

 

in situ

         

T FREQ

verb AD

verb AD

ísékà verb

AD li verb

ex situ

T ORDINAL

verb vbi AD

verb vbi AD

 

AD li verb

ex situ

           

T DEIXIS

verb AD

verb AD

éghè re verb

AD li verb

ex situ

T BOUND

verb vbi AD

re AD verb

     

T QUANT

verb AD

re AD verb

íkpédè ékà re verb

 

ex situ

           

LOCATIVE

verb vbi AD

verb vbi AD

ébé' za verb

AD li za verb

ex situ

           

REASON

re AD verb

re AD verb

 

AD li re verb

ex situ

Table 2: Coding of Emai adjunct (AD) types (where A is Aspectual and T is Temporal) by verbs se, tee, re, and za relative to clause types declarative (DECL), imperative (IMP), interrogative (INTER), contrastive focus (CF) and response to information question (R-Q).

At the outset we noted in passing Croft’s (2001) comparison of adjunct and argument semantic character. His semantic analysis emphasizes adjuncts as relations relative to their associated predication, following theoretical arguments laid out by Langacker (1987: 214-216), who posits a relation as existing when the definition of one concept inherently requires reference to another concept. If adjuncts are inherently relations, they are functions, i.e. predicates, that take an argument. With reference to (24), in the park is then a predicate whose single argument is the event of chasing. One and the same semantic component, i,e, chase, can thus be a relation or a filler argument of a role in a relation. While chasing is a relation with George and dog as filler arguments, chasing is also a filler argument for the relation being-in-the-park.

(24) George chased the dog in the park.

Earlier, we identified two questions that derive from Croft’s analysis and illustration. Do all adjunct types lead to consistent morphosyntactic expression across clause types? And do all adjuncts manifest similar distributional potential? More importantly for Croft’s analysis is a third question: Is there morphosyntactic evidence to support the claim that an adjunct is a relation and so can take an associated event as filler argument?

Recall Croft’s position that adjuncts are relations taking as their filler argument a matrix clause event. The facts from Emai suggest that not all adjunct constituents are relations vis-à-vis the matrix predicate, i.e. predicates that take a matrix event as filler. Instead, a number of adjunct types appear to be filler arguments for a latent verb that under varying discourse conditions appears in series in the matrix predicate phrase. It is these filler adjunct types, locative and temporal deixis for example, and their latent verbs, za and re respectively, that as a relation could take the matrix clause event as filler.

Not all adjunct expressions serve as filler argument for a latent verb however. Some appear to be relations that could directly take the matrix predicate as filler. The clearest example of this adjunct type is manner; adjuncts expressing temporal frequency and temporal ordinal sequence also appear to be examplars of this type.

Based on these distribution facts from Emai, one could formulate a relation-filler cline for adjuncts in which the propensity to serve as a filler argument increases while the propensity to serve as a relation decreases. The most comprehensive filler adjunct would be REASON, which requires the verb re in all clauses where its exponents occur. The next most filler-like adjunct would be LOCATIVE, which requires latent verb za in contrastive focus and interrogative clauses. The least filler-like and most relation-like adjunct would be MANNER, which revealed no latent verb. TEMPORAL would clearly be the most inconsistent class since temporal frequency and temporal ordinal evince no latent verb, while temporal deixis, temporal quantity and temporal bound lead to latent verb re in either interrogative or imperative clauses or both.

MANNER < TEMPORAL < LOCATIVE < REASON

Extent adjuncts, however, exhibit unique properties, as shown by their interrogative frame. They manifest a correspondence relation to not only an information question word (ébé' ‘how’) and its preverb í but also a latent verb (se) or verbs (se, tee) in postpredicate position, neither of which surfaces in imperative or contrastive focus clauses. The syntactic position of latent verbs associated with extent adjuncts thus contrasts with the position of latent verbs for locative and temporal adjuncts.

Extent adjuncts would be troublesome for a relation-filler cline. They consistently require a latent verb (or verbs) in interrogative clauses but position it after, not before, the matrix predicate. Where would extent adjuncts best fit on a relation-filler cline? Moreover, one wonders whether there might be other linguistic evidence that would identify structural affinities between or among Emai adjunct types. One fact to consider in this regard is shape of adjunct response frame relative to its information question. In question-answer discourse contexts, many adjunct types occur in response to an information question as phrases isolated from clause structure, i.e. ex situ as summarized in Table 2 and exemplified in (7), (8b), (13b) and (17c). Three adjunct types, aspectual extent, temporal extent and manner, fail this test however; each requires an in situ frame in which the respective adjunct follows its matrix verb, as in (19c), (22b) and (23c), repeated here as (25), (26) and (27).

(25)

ébé'

ójé

í'

ánmé

óí

étò

sé?

 

how

Oje

PAP.MAN

scrape

her

hair

extend.to

 

‘To what extent did Oje scrape her hair?’

 

ó

ì

ànmè

óí

étó

á

gbègbéí.

 

he

NEG

scrape

her

hair

CS

completely

 

‘He did not scrape her hair completely.

(26)

ébé'

ó

ómó

í'

mùzàn

téé

sè?

 

how

the

man

PAP.MAN

wait

be.long

extend.to

 

‘How long did the man wait?’

 

 

ó

múzán-í'

títítí.

 

he

PAP.wait-F

long.time

 

‘He waited for a long time.’

(27)

ébé'

ó

ómó

ó

ò

í

è

émàè?

 

how

the

man

SC

H

MAN

eat

food

 

‘How does the man eat food?’

   

 

ó

ò

è

óí

kóíkóí.

 

he

H

eat

it

gulpingly

 

‘He gulps it.’

In situ responses as well as interrogative proform in information questions (ébé' and i) thus suggest that adjuncts with a postpredicate latent verb are similar to adjuncts that reveal no latent verb; both are more relation like than filler like. Clearly, a simple correlation between morphosyntactic properties and adjunct status as relation or filler is not straightforward.[10] Nonetheless, it does appear that while all adjunct expressions may be relational, not all adjuncts are relations. Some adjuncts are fillers that require a latent verb, especially in clause types outside the canonical declarative.

References

Croft, William. 2001. Radical construction grammar. New York: Oxford University Press.

Elugbe, Ben. 1989. Comparative Edoid: Phonology and lexicon. Port Harcourt: University of Port Harcourt Press.

Langacker, Ronald. W. 1987. Foundations of cognitive grammar, Vol I: Theoretical perspectives. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Matthews, Peter H. 1981. Syntax. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

-----. 2007. Syntactic relations. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Schaefer, Ronald P. and Francis O. Egbokhare. 1999. Oral tradition narratives of the Emai people, Part I and Part II. Hamburg: LIT Verlag.

-----. 2000. Emai preverb order. Proceedings of the 2nd World Congress of African Linguistics, Lepzig 1997, ed. by H. Ekkehard Wolff and Orin D. Gensler, 733-746. Cologne: Rüdiger Köppe Verlag.

-----. 2007. A dictionary of Emai: An Edoid language of Nigeria. Cologne: Rüdiger Köppe Verlag.

-----. 2010. On Emai ditransitive constructions. Studies in ditransitive constructions: A comparative handbook, ed. by Andrej Malchukov, Martin Haspelmath and Bernard Comrie, 115-145. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.

-----. To appear. A reference grammar for Emai: A Nigerian Edoid language. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

Watters, John. R. 2000. Syntax. African languages: An introduction, ed. by Bernd Heine and Derek Nurse, 194-230. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Williamson, Kay and Roger Blench. 2000. Niger Congo. African languages: An introduction, ed. by Bernd Heine and Derek Nurse, 11-42. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Author’s Contact Information (corresponding author):

 

 

 

Ronald P. Schaefer
Center for International Programs
Southern Illinois University Edwardsville
Edwardsville, IL 62026-1616
rschaef@siue.edu

Francis O. Egbokhare
Department of Linguistics and African Languages
University of Ibadan
Ibadan, Nigeria
foegbokhare@yahoo.com

 

 


[1]Data incorporated in this paper derive from research sponsored by the National Science Foundation, (BNS #9011338 and SBR #9409552), the U.S. Department of State (College and University Affiliations Program grant ASJY 1333), Southern Illinois University Edwardsville, particularly its Distinguished Research Professor award, and the University of Ibadan, Nigeria, particularly its Inaugural Lecture series. We thank these institutions for their continued support, while not extending to them any responsibility for our data interpretation.

[2]Orthographic conventions for Emai generally reflect Schaefer and Egbokhare (2007), where o represents a lax mid back vowel, e a lax mid front vowel, and vb a voiced bilabial approximant. For tone, acute accent marks high, grave signals low, and acute followed by an apostrophe designates high downstep. Abbreviations for grammatical morphemes used in this paper include: APP = applicative, ASS = associative, C = continuous, CL = change of location, CS = change of state, F = factative, H = habitual, ID = identity pronoun, IND = indicative, LOC = locative, MAN = manner, NEG = negative, NF = negative focus, PAP = past perfect, PF = positive focus, PRP = present perfect, R = relator, SC = subject concord, TEMP = temporal perspective.

[3]It is worthwhile to note that English adjuncts differ in morphosyntactic expression as well, e.g. noun preceded by a preposition (in the park) versus lexical adverb (clumsily).

[4]Evidence that za and re are verbs and not preverbs emerges from tonal behavior in Present Perfect aspect (Schaefer and Egbokhare to appear), where verb phrase initial monosyllabic preverbs like Additive gbo ‘too, also’ (in addition to auxiliaries) show a high low falling tone (òjè gbóò híán óràn [Oje ADD PRP.cut wood] ‘Oje has cut wood too’) but phrase initial monosyllabic verbs do not (òjè gbé ófè [Oje PRP.kill rat] ‘Oje has killed a rat’ not *òjè gbéè ófè).

[5]Temporal deictic adjuncts occur in contrastive focus position, òdèóómóhé é' ólí émàè [yesterday PF the man PAP.eat the food] ‘It was yesterday that the man ate the food,’ although not with a latent verb in series. Temporal deictic òdè does not occur in imperative clauses; other deictic adjuncts, e.g. ákhò ‘tomorrow’ and éè ‘today,’ do, though not with a latent verb.

[6]Temporal ordinal adjuncts occur in information question clauses with a complex structure, although not one involving a latent verb in series. Ordinal adjuncts correspond to a question frame marked by the identity pronoun í ID and the verb yi ‘identify’ and its complement noun édè ‘day.’ Ordinal adjuncts thus do not correspond to éghè re interrogatives, as temporal deictic adjuncts do.

(i)

í

édé

ó

híán'

ó

óràn?

 

ID

identify

day

R

he

PAP.cut

the

wood

 

‘On which day did he cut the wood?

 

úkpédé

ózèéà.

 

day

R

third

 

‘On the third day.’

[7]Reason adjuncts correspond to the complex interrogative frame émé' ó ze khi ‘why,’ which does not involve a latent verb in series. Instead, the erstwhile matrix clause occurs in an embedded indicative marked clause (indicative complement khi) under a cause verb, i.e. ze. It is this matrix cause verb that syntactically corresponds to the reason adjunct.

(i)

émé'

ó

zé-í'

khí

ó

ómó

é'

ó

émàè

léé?

 

what

it

PAP.cause-F

IND

the

man

PAP.eat

the

food

TEMP

 

‘What caused the man to finish eating the food?

   

 

òó

ísì

òhànmì.

 

cause

ASS

hunger

 

‘Because of hunger.’

[8]That manner i is a synchronic preverb, not a verb, is supported by its distribution. It never occurs as a simple predicate, transitive or intransitive, or as one constituent of a complex predicate. It arises only in manner expressions where a manner related constituent has been fronted, e.g. manner demonstrative adjunct (ìyá ‘that way,’ ìná ‘this way’) or with information question word ébé' ‘how.’ In contrast, se, za and re occur as simple predicates or as constituents of complex predicates (Schaefer and Egbokhare to appear).

[9]Temporal extent adjuncts fail to occur in contrastive focus and imperative clauses, as the examples below illustrate.

(i)

*tìtìtì

ó

ómó

múzán'-ì.

 

long.time

PF

the

man

PAP.wait-F

 

‘It was for a long time that the man waited.’

(ii)

*mùzàn

títítí.

 

wait

long.time

 

‘Wait a long time.’

[10]The correlation between position of latent verb relative to matrix verb, i.e. preceding vs following matrix predicate, and shape of interrogative response allowed, i.e. in situ vs ex situ, suggests that a more complex parameter than relation/argument may be operating. For the moment, however, we leave this notion unexplored.

[ Home | Current Issue | Browse the Archive | Search the Site | Submission Information | Register for Updates | About | Editorial Board | Site Map | Help ]

Published by the Dartmouth College Library.
Copyright © 2002 Trustees of Dartmouth College.
For comments or feedback E-mail the site editor.
ISSN 1537-0852

Linguistic Discovery HomeDartmouth College Home