Volume 10 Issue 3 (2012)
DOI:10.1349/PS1.1537-0852.A.413
Note: Linguistic Discovery uses Unicode characters
to represent phonetic symbols. Please see Optimizing Display
for requirements to accurately reproduce this page.
Referential Effects on the Expression of Three-Participant Events across Languages
An Introduction in Memory of Anna Siewierska
Eva van Lier
University of
Amsterdam
1. Background
of the Current Issue
The majority of the papers collected in
this special issue were presented at the Workshop on referential hierarchies in
three-participant constructions, held at Lancaster University in May 2011. Two
papers - on Yakima Sahaptin by Joana Jansen and on Araki by Alexandre
François - were not presented at the workshop, but originated in
the same context: a research project on referential hierarchies in
three-participant constructions, carried out by the workshop organizers: Anna
Siewierska and myself, the guest editor of the current issue.
It was with great sadness that we, the authors of
the papers collected here, heard of Anna-s sudden death in a car accident
in Vietnam, on August 6th 2011, just a few months after we had
convened in Lancaster. I wish to dedicate this special issue to the memory of
Anna, who was the principle investigator of the project that inspired its
creation. I also wish to thank Lindsay Whaley, the editor of
Linguistic
Discovery
, for giving me the chance to complete this issue in Anna's
honor.
The project on referential hierarchies in
three-participant constructions is part of a larger project on Referential
Hierarchies in Morpho-Syntax (RHIM), which is in turn one of the EuroBABEL
projects funded by the European Science Foundation. The EuroBABEL initiative
promotes empirical research on endangered languages, with the aim of advancing
our knowledge of linguistic structure in general
. The funding of the
workshop in Lancaster by the EuroBABEL organization is gratefully
acknowledged.
I believe - and I am sure I can speak on
behalf of Anna too - that the workshop in Lancaster and the current issue
reflect fruitful collaboration in more than one respect. Most importantly, I am
deeply grateful to the authors of the papers on endangered languages for the
effort they have put into collecting first-hand data on the intricate details of
referential effects in three-participant constructions, and for their
willingness to share their expertise with Anna and me. At the same time, I think
that our cross-linguistic perspective has helped colleagues working on
individual languages to ask questions that otherwise might have remained
unanswered. This cross-fertilization has been indispensable for the development
of our understanding of the theory and typology of referential effects on
three-participant constructions.
The current issue contains contributions on
languages from different geographical and genetic backgrounds. Many of these are
languages studied by members of the RHIM project (this holds for Blackfoot,
Yakima Sahaptin, and Movima), but a second EuroBABEL project on Alor-Pantar
languages is also represented (see the paper by Marian Klamer and Antoinette
Schapper). In addition, the projects on endangered languages have inspired
further investigation of an extremely well-studied language like Spanish (see
the paper by Chiyo Nishida).
This introductory paper outlines some of the
theoretical and typological notions that constitute the common ground behind the
case studies collected in this issue. This common ground is situated at the
intersection of two research domains: referential hierarchies and
three-participant constructions. First, in section 2, I discuss referential
conditions on argument coding from the general perspective of alignment in one-
and two-participant constructions. I also consider the additional conditioning
factor of lexical predicate class. Sections 3 to 6 are specifically concerned
with three-participant constructions; their definition (section 3), referential
effects on their argument encoding (section 4), and interaction with lexical
factors (section 5). The overview on three-participant constructions is rounded
off with a brief summary (section 6). Finally, in section (7) I introduce the
individual papers that constitute the body of this issue.
2.
Referential and Lexical Conditions on Argument Coding
Ever since Silverstein (1976), the
effects of referential properties on argument realization have been widely
studied (for an overview see for instance Witzlack-Makarevich 2011, chapter 6).
From the perspective of the current issue, two aspects of such referential
effects are of particular importance.
First, there is a range of different types of
referential properties, each of which involves several different values. These
values can be hierarchically ordered with respect to each other, in terms of how
they affect argument encoding, as represented in
(1):[1]
(1)
|
a.
|
pronoun > noun
|
|
b.
|
proper noun > common noun
|
|
c.
|
1st/2nd person >
3rd person
|
|
d.
|
human > non-human animate >
inanimate
|
|
e.
|
specific > non-specific referential >
generic/non-referential
|
|
f.
|
definite > indefinite
|
|
g.
|
singular > plural
|
|
h.
|
topical > non-topical
|
Notably, the referential factors in (1a-h) are not
homogeneous; they reflect inherent categories (e.g. humanness), syntactic
categories (e.g. (pro)nominality) and discourse-related categories (e.g.
topicality). Nonetheless, (some of) the individual hierarchies have been
presented in integrated or nested fashion. Also, both separated and combined
versions of hierarchies have featured in the literature under a variety of names
(see e.g. Bickel 2010: 410 and Witzlack-Makarevich 2011: 89 for examples and
references). Here I will use the general term
referential properties to
refer to the factors and their values listed in (1), and the term
referential
effects
to refer to the way(s) in which these properties affect argument
encoding.
Concerning the specific form that referential effects may take , several predictions have been formulated in
the literature. For case marking, it has been hypothesized that referentially
high-ranking agents and low-ranking patients have higher chances of being
zero-marked (Comrie 1989). According to an alternative interpretation, this
prediction concerns distributionally unmarked nominative and absolutive case
forms: high-ranking participants are expected to show nominative alignment, and
low-ranking participants to show absolutive alignment (Silverstein 1976).
However, recent testing of these predictions against large typological data sets
provides only weak statistical support (see Bickel 2008, Bickel &
Witzlack-Makarevich 2008).
As for agreement marking, it has been predicted that
referentially high-ranking participants are more likely to trigger agreement
than low-ranking participants. While this expectation is born out for agents,
this is not the case for patients, which may also show the reverse pattern, at
least as far as the factor of person is concerned (Siewierska 2004: 149
ff).
In general, however, the common principle behind
referential effects, and behind the hierarchies in (1a-h) appears to be the
following: if grammatical relations in a certain language have restricted access
depending on referential properties, then participants with referential
properties on the high (i.e. left) end of the hierarchies in (1) are more likely
to have such access than participants with lower-ranking properties (i.e. more
to the right in (1)) (Bickel 2008, 2010). At the same time, individual languages
and constructions will vary as to exactly which referential properties are
relevant.
A second issue of particular relevance to the theme
of the current issue is how referential restrictions are -applied-
in a particular construction of a particular language; more specifically,
whether argument realization is determined on the basis of the referential
properties of a single participant, or whether the properties of two (or more)
participants must be taken into account. The former case is typically referred
to as
differential marking. It has been discussed mostly in the context
of (dependent) marking of patient arguments, commonly known as
differential
object marking
(Bossong 1985, Aissen 2003), but it is relevant also for
other types of argument encoding, namely
differential subject marking
(DeLancey 1991, Dixon 1994, de Hoop & de Swart 2009),
differential
recipient/goal marking
(Haspelmath 2007, Kittilä 2008), and
differential theme marking (Haspelmath 2007, Malchukov
2008).
In contrast to differential marking, which is based
on the properties of a single participant, argument realization may be
co-argument conditioned, i.e. dependent on the referential properties of
more than one participant.[2]
A
specific constellation of multiple participants with certain referential
properties is called a
scenario (following Z--iga 2006,
Bickel 2010). The classical example of
co-argument conditioned marking is
a system that has been termed
hierarchical alignment or, more
specifically,
hierarchical agreement (Nichols 1992, Siewierska 2004). It
involves competition between two participants for a specific type of
morpho-syntactic treatment; typically indexation by means of verbal inflection.
The participant with the highest-ranking referential properties wins this
competition, regardless of its role. Additional marking on the verb can indicate
whether the action proceeds from a higher to a lower-ranking participant
(
direct) or from a lower to higher-ranking one (
inverse). This
type of system is attested for instance in the Algonquian language Blackfoot
(see Russell et al., this issue).
However, there are many other variants of
co-argument conditioned marking systems, as is evident from almost all the
papers in the present issue. It is important to realize that not all of these
systems are hierarchical in the sense that argument realization is based on the
relative referential properties of two participants, with the higher one
outranking the lower one. It is also possible that the marker used to encode a
specific argument varies depending on the nature of its co-argument, without
involving competition for the same marker. As argued by Witzlack-Makarevich and
colleagues (2011), the crucial characteristic of co-argument conditioned
alignment resides in its being based on the properties of more than one
argument, and classical hierarchical systems represent just one of multiple
options in this domain.
From the perspective of alignment typology,
referential effects present a challenge: there is no straightforward way to
compare argument realization across one-, two-, and three-participant
constructions in order to determine basic alignment patterns, since the encoding
of S, A, P, T, and G roles (to be defined below) depends on referential factors.
For splits in the form of differential marking, the solution would be to compare
only participants with the same referential values. However, this is impossible
in the case of co-argument conditioned argument realization, where the encoding
of each argument-type can only be defined in terms of its co-occurrence with
another argument-type. Witzlack-Makarevich et al. (2011) propose to solve this
problem by cross-comparing argument realization in all possible scenario types
and calculating proportions of scenarios that display specific alignment
patterns.
The same line of research addresses a similar
problem associated with a different type of condition on argument coding:
lexical predicate class (see Bickel et al. 2010). In many languages, individual
predicates show different argument realization frames. Again, the question
arises as to how this variation can be accounted for in alignment typology. A
frequently practiced solution is to determine alignment patterns on the basis of
-default- predicate classes in a particular language (see Haspelmath
2011). However, apart from the fact that it is not straightforward which
criteria should be used to determine such default classes, this approach boils
down to ignoring an important part of the attested variation: the behavior of
all the non-default predicate classes. Therefore, Bickel and colleagues use a
method that is related to the one proposed for co-argument conditioned systems:
they compare argument realization across different types of lexical classes, and
calculate alignment patterns proportionally.
In sum, typological investigations of referential
and lexical effects on argument realization reveal a wide range of diversity. In
particular, to compare the expression of arguments across different
constructions in specific languages one must take into account (i) the
referential properties of these arguments and potentially also of their possible
co-arguments, and (ii) the specific lexical predicates or predicate classes
involved. The following sections will show how the challenges that arise in the
analysis of one- and two-participant constructions (the basic constructions
involved in alignment theory and typology) are relevant for three-participant
constructions as well.
3.
Definition of Three-Participant Constructions
For the purpose of the current issue, a
three-participant construction is defined as a construction that expresses a
three-participant event, which is in turn defined by Margetts and Austin (2007:
397) as a -dynamic state of affairs that crucially involves three entities
in its conceptualization-. It should be noted that this definition is
wider than the one employed by Malchukov et al. (2010:1), who restrict their
scope to
ditransitive constructions, which involve an agent, a theme (T),
and recipient-like (R) argument. Even though the latter definition includes some
-less central- recipients, like the addressee of mental transfer
verbs (such as -show- and -tell-), it excludes other
types of three-participant constructions such as those in which the third
participant is a spatial goal rather than a recipient, as with events of
putting. While the latter type of three-participant constructions are included
in the definition employed here, this does not mean that all papers in the
current issue cover the same broad range of construction types. Some indeed
include event-types like putting, but others focus on construction types
corresponding to ditransitive constructions
as defined by Malchukov and
colleagues.
Our definition of three-participant constructions is
in keeping with the semantic approach to argumenthood proposed by Bickel and
Nichols (2009) and Bickel (2010). In this approach, generalized argument roles
are defined, firstly, in terms of the number of participants implied by the
meaning of the verb. Thus, S is the sole argument of a one-participant verb. If
the event expressed by the verb implies the involvement of more than one
participant, the relevant argument roles are distinguished as follows: A is the
more agent-like argument and P the less agent-like argument of a two-participant
verb. With three-participant verbs, the T argument corresponds to the
transferred or moved participant, while G is the participant towards which the
transfer action is directed.
Notably, since some of the papers in this issue
restrict their discussion to three-participant events that involve a
recipient-like G argument (and don-t take into account other types of Gs,
such as locational goals), these papers employ R instead of G, where R can be
regarded as a sub-type of the generalized G-role. In addition, there is some
variation between the papers with respect to the term used for the less
agent-like argument of a two-participant verb, which is sometimes referred to as
O rather than P, following the Dixonian tradition. Unlike the G/R variation,
however, the P/O alternation is just a matter of notational
convention.[3]
Since the 1980-s (Dryer 1986; Croft 1990;
Siewierska 2003, 2004, Haspelmath 2004, 2007; Malchukov et al. 2010),
three-participant constructions have been included in alignment theory and
typology (although in various terminological guises). The basic
ditransitive
alignment
patterns represented in (2), together with their
intransitive/monotransitive counterparts, are in current use and are referenced
in this issue. Note that the term
ditransitive alignment is not meant to
imply that these alignment types are applicable only to
ditransitive
constructions
as defined by Malchukov et al. (2010). Rather, these alignment
types are applicable to three-participant constructions in general, but I will
nonetheless use the term
ditransitive alignment as a convenient short
hand.
4.
Referential Effects on Three-Participant Constructions
Referential effects on argument
realization and alignment in three-participant constructions have been studied
from cross-linguistic and language-specific perspectives. In general, however,
this topic has received relatively little attention, probably because most
ditransitive constructions (as defined by Malchukov et al. 2010; see above)
involve T arguments that rank low on the referential hierarchies listed in (1)
above, while R arguments tend to rank high. This holds specifically for
ditransitive verbs of the -give- type, which have dominated research
in three-participant constructions from the lexical side. Nonetheless, there are
a number of exceptions to these biases, which I will briefly review in the
remainder of this section.
Firstly, three-participant constructions with
referentially high-ranking Ts have been studied - often from generative
and alternative formal perspectives - in relation to the so-called
Person Role Constraint (see e.g Perlmutter 1971; Bonet 1994;
Anagnostopoulou 2003; Ormazabal & Romero 2007). In the Romance languages,
where this was first noted, the constraint defines a dis-preference for
1st or 2nd person Ts, which is formally reflected by the
use of a relatively complex prepositional construction (as in 3a), rather than a
sequence of two clitics (as in 3b):
French
(quoted in Haspelmath 2004:
2)
(3)
|
a.
|
Agnés
|
me
|
presenterá
|
a
|
elle.
|
|
|
Agnes |
1SG.ACC |
introduce.FUT.3SG |
PREP |
3SG.FEM. |
|
|
'Agnes will introduce me to
her.' |
|
b.
|
Agnés
|
me
|
la
|
presenterá
|
|
|
|
Agnes |
1SG.DAT |
3SG.FEM.ACC |
introduce.FUT.3SG |
|
|
|
'Agnes will introduce her to
me.' |
Cross-linguistic research (Haspelmath 2004) shows
that the Person Role Constraint is not restricted to the scenario represented in
(3a) - where the 1st person T outranks the 3rd
person G on the referential hierarchy of person (see (1c) above) - but in
some languages also obtains when T and G have equal ranking, i.e. when they are
both 3rd persons or both speech act participants (1st or
2nd persons). In other languages the constraint is shown to extend
beyond the person hierarchy, and to ultimately reflect a general preference for
G to have higher-ranking referential properties than
T.[4]
Notably, this constraint takes
into account the relative referential properties of T and G, and as such relates
to co-argument conditioned marking. Drawing the parallel with co-argument
conditioned marking in monotransitive constructions, Haspelmath (2007) uses the
term
inverse ditransitive patterns for the expression of scenarios in
which the referential properties of T and G go against the expected pattern of G
outranking T.
Closely related to Haspelmath's work is
Kittilä's (2006) study on three-participant constructions involving
two human non-agents. However, rather than taking the perspective of discourse
frequency, Kittilä focuses on the distinguishability of the T and G roles,
in relation to different types of non-agent encoding strategies employed by
individual languages. In particular, if a language displays an
object-based
or
animacy-based strategy, this potentially gives rise to ambiguity:
a human T and a human G would be coded in the same way, either by virtue of
their being objects or because of their being human. This potential formal
ambiguity can be resolved in different ways, such as the use of a prepositional
construction, parallel to what we saw in French in (3a) above. In contrast,
there are also languages that use a
role-based marking strategy. In these
languages T and G are always marked distinctly - independently of
objecthood and referential properties - because they have different
semantic roles. In these languages no ambiguity arises when T and G are both
human, and therefore no special formal measures are expected.
The findings of Haspelmath's and
Kittiläs studies are broadly confirmed in the work by Siewierska and
Van Lier (2012a, b). Using a combination of corpus data and cross-linguistic
questionnaires, they investigate the expression of three-participant events with
two human non-agents (T and G) within and across different languages. They find
(very) low frequencies of relatively high-ranking Ts, and morpho-syntactic
repercussions of this non-prototypicality in the form of relatively more complex
and otherwise deviant expression
strategies.[5]
As for ambiguity
avoidance, it is shown that while languages with role-based (as opposed to
object-based or animacy-based) marking display fewer formal effects of
non-prototypical scenarios, this does not mean that such effects are completely
absent. This suggests that both discourse infrequency and ambiguity-avoidance
play a role in explaining the attested variation. Furthermore, Siewierska and
Van Lier point out lexical effects on the expression of (non-prototypical)
three-participant events; a topic to which I return in section
5.
Apart from co-argument conditioned coding in
three-participant constructions, several studies have considered the referential
properties of T or G in isolation, and the effects of these properties on
argument realization. As far as G is concerned, Haspelmath (2007) and
Kittilä (2008) both investigate the cross-linguistic expression of
different referential types of Gs. However, as with co-argument conditioned
argument realization, they take slightly different perspectives and offer
slightly different explanations for the attested patterns. According to
Haspelmath (2007: 83) "special R-marking is more likely, the lower the R
is in the animacy, definiteness, and person scales." Such special marking
involves "indirective or dative" marking, and is interpreted as a
formal reflex of the non-prototypicality (i.e. discourse infrequency) of Rs with
low-ranking referential properties. A parallel argumentation is proposed for
special marking of high-ranking Ts, even though this phenomenon is claimed to be
much less frequently attested across languages.
While Haspelmath investigates whether specific
referential properties trigger special R-marking, Kittilä (2008)
investigates different ways of coding animate as opposed to inanimate Gs, in
comparison to animate and inanimate Ps. In two out of the three types of coding
patterns distinguished in Kittiläs study, animate Gs are expressed
in the same way as animate Ps. Therefore, he explains both differential
G-marking and differential P-marking in terms of affectedness: the equal marking
of animate Ps and Gs reflect their status as the primary affected targets in
two- and three-participant events, respectively. This marking contrasts with the
encoding of inanimate Gs, which are rather expressed as obliques.
Kittiläs third type of coding system also involves oblique marking
of inanimate Gs, but this does not contrast with -core- marking of
animate Gs, since this type of system always encodes Ps differently from Gs. In
sum, while the cross-linguistic data presented by Haspelmath and Kittilä
are compatible, their distinct respective foci are reflected in the different
types of functional explanations they propose.
In parallel with the previous section, this brief
review of studies about referential effects on argument realization and
alignment in three-participant constructions outlines a broad spectrum of
variability. As Malchukov et al. (2010: 7) remark, -the identification of
ditransitive alignment pattern requires that we identify a major monotransitive
construction so that we know what the monotransitive P is that we compare the
ditransitive T and R with. This is not straightforward if there is a major split
in the coding of monotransitives.- Malchukov and colleagues choose to
-adopt the most typical transitive construction, with an inanimate,
indefinite P as the major monotransitive construction-.
This approach, however, is problematic. Firstly, it
is not straightforward to choose a specific referential type of P as the
standard of comparison. The same holds for T and G to the extent that each may
have various referential properties, along several referential dimensions.
Second, we have seen that the encoding of P, T, and G may depend not only on the
referential properties of each of these participants considered in isolation,
but also on the properties of their co-arguments. More generally, comparing the
prototypical three-participant scenario (involving a low-ranking T and a
high-ranking G) with the prototypical two-participant scenario (involving a
high-ranking A and a low-ranking P) leads to the exclusion of a large proportion
of the attested variation.
This is especially true for the type of languages
that are at the focus of attention in the present issue, namely those in which
argument realization is primarily conditioned or at least pervasively influenced
by referential factors. In addition, it would seem that three-participant
constructions have a special potential for co-argument conditioned argument
marking to come into play, as there are two non-agentive participants that may
compete for (a certain type of) P-like morpho-syntactic treatment. As Bickel and
Witzlack-Makarevich show, the solutions proposed for parallel problems with the
determination of alignment in one- and two-participant constructions (see
section 2) are applicable to three-participant constructions as well (Bickel et
al. 2010, Witzlack-Makarevich et al. 2011). This holds not only for referential
effects, but also for lexical effects, to which I turn in the next
section.
5.
Three-Participant Constructions and the Lexicon
A second important source of variation
in three-participant constructions is lexical predicate class. In fact, the
lexical factor appears to be relatively strong in three-participant
constructions, as compared to two-participant constructions: "While all
languages have a substantial class of transitive verbs that behave uniformly,
some languages have only a handful of ditransitive verbs, and not uncommonly
these do not behave uniformly" (Malchukov 2010:2). Moreover, the lexical
factor becomes increasingly prominent with the wider definition of
three-participant constructions employed here.
Within the domain of lexical effects on argument
encoding, a distinction can be made between
splits and
alternations. The former term refers to the 'purely lexical'
phenomenon that a certain groups of verbs in a specific language selects one
type of argument expression frame while another verb class selects another. The
term
alternation is used, by contrast, when the same lexical verb -
or class of verbs - can occur with more than one argument expression
frame.
With alternations, the choice for one or the other
construction is influenced by multiple factors; among them referential factors
of the type discussed above. Bresnan and colleagues (2007 and later work)
extensively studied the
dative alternation in English, using corpus data.
The application of multiple-regression modeling allows these authors to assess
the relative contribution to construction choice of a number of referential
factors, including definiteness, animacy, and anaphoricity, which show pervasive
partial correlations. This method also allows teasing apart the effects of
referential factors on the one hand - specifically anaphoricity and
topicality - and
heaviness or relative complexity of the T and G
arguments on the other hand (cf. Wasow 2002).
Another condition on the choice between alternating
argument realization frames concerns the different semantic meanings associated
with specific construction types. For the English dative alternation, it has
been proposed that the double object construction expresses caused possession
meaning, while the prepositional construction has caused motion semantics
(Goldberg 1995). More recently however, Rappaport Hovav and Levin (2008), have
argued that whether the dative alternation has a semantic impact or whether it
is rather referentially determined depends on the particular verb. Specifically,
'send'-type verbs are claimed to have caused possession meaning only
when they occur with the double object construction and caused motion meaning
when they occur with the prepositional construction. In contrast,
'give'-type verbs have caused possession meaning in both
construction types. With these latter verbs, the dative alternation is triggered by
factors of the type identified by Bresnan and colleagues.
Further corpus-based research on the dative
alternation - e.g. Gries and Stefanowitsch (2004) for English and Colleman
(2009) for Dutch - points to differences between individual verbs in terms
of constructional preferences, i.e. whether a specific alternating verb occurs
significantly more often in one or the other construction. Colleman (2009)
focuses on semantic factors influencing such preferences in Dutch, suggesting
that certain verbs are more strongly oriented towards the effect of the action
on the G-participant, whereas other verbs are T-oriented. This semantic
principle potentially cross-cuts other semantic classifications of
three-participant verbs (cf. Levin 1993). For instance, within the class of
communication verbs
in Dutch, the verb
aanraden
'advise' is arguably most concerned with the effect of the
action on the addressee (G), whereas
bekendmaken 'announce'
is more about a change in the state of T. This difference would explain why
aanraden typically occurs in the double object construction, while
bekendmaken is found most often with the prepositional
construction.
Malchukov et al. (2010: 20) interpret this type of
semantic difference in terms of the
affectedness of the T and G argument,
respectively. Since affectedness and referential factors like animacy typically
co-vary, we see again that different factors conditioning alternations are
easily confounded. In other words, the constructional preferences of specific
lexical verbs may be (partially) caused by the referential properties of the
participants that these verbs tend to co-occur with. In a recent attempt to
assess this problem, De Swart, Van Bergen and Van Lier (2011) conducted a
production experiment in Dutch, involving alternating verbs with different
constructional preferences (based on Colleman's (2006, 2009) corpus data),
combined with identical scenarios, i.e. with the same sets of referential
T/G-types. The results of this study indicate that constructional preferences of
individual lexical verbs exist independently of the referential properties of
non-agentive participants.
Another point that emerges from research on the
dative alternation concerns micro-level lexical differences, both between
languages and within languages. Colleman-s work mentioned above (2009:
693) shows that while semantic factors driving the alternation in English and
Dutch are
grosso modo the same, this does not mean that translational
equivalents in these two languages display the same constructional behavior.
Looking at alternation within a single language, Ormazabal and Romero (2007)
remark that Spanish
enviar and
mandar - both verbs meaning
'send' - pattern differently with respect to the use of two
clitics, as opposed to a prepositional construction: in scenarios with two human
pronominal non-agents, two clitics are more widely used with
enviar than
with
mandar (see also Nishida, this issue, for micro-level lexical
effects in Spanish).
Lexical effects concern not only constructional
choice with alternating verbs, but also involve altogether distinct verb
classes. In the latter case, we are dealing with lexical
splits.
Malchukov et al. (2010: 48ff) investigate general patterns of lexical splits
across languages, trying to find out whether it is "possible to establish
a predisposition of semantic verb classes for specific alignment patterns [and
to] make predictions concerning how a verb with a particular meaning will
pattern cross-linguistically." Their results show patterns of identical
marking of certain three-participant event-types, as expressed by individual
lexical verbs. For instance, if allative marking is used for the G-role in
prototypical ditransitive constructions of the 'give' type, then
this marking extends to verbs of caused motion, such as 'send' and
'throw.'
Just like construction alternations, lexical splits
show both macro- and micro-level variation. While Malchukov and colleagues
identify broad cross-linguistic patterns, there are also subtle differences
between closely related languages and between verb classes in a single language.
For example, Siewierska and Van Lier (2012b) find that certain English verbs
that occur relatively frequently with two human non-agents (such as
introduce)
belong to the class that combines exclusively with the
prepositional construction. In Dutch, the translational equivalents of these
verbs (such as
voorstellen)
rather belong to the alternating
class, even though in scenarios with two human non-agents the double object
construction is systematically avoided.
Further examples are provided by the studies in the
current issue: in some languages apparently near-synonymous verbs belong to
different predicate classes with distinct alignment patterns. Blackfoot, for
instance, has two verb stems meaning 'give',
ohkot- and
omatska-, of which the former always indexes G, while the latter indexes
only T (see Russell et al., this issue). Similarly, in Movima we find one verb
'ask'
daj<a:>wa with secundative alignment and another
verb 'ask'
daja:ja with indirective alignment (see Haude,
this issue). Arguably, as was the case with alternating verbs, these lexical
splits are motivated in terms of whether the verb meaning highlights the
affectedness of G or T.
A final locus of lexical variation, which is not
taken into account in the typological overview by Malchukov et al. (2010),
involves derived three-participant constructions, more specifically applicative
and causative constructions. It is often assumed that the applied participant
and the causee are morpho-syntactically treated like a monotransitive P
(Peterson 2007). However, several papers in this issue show that there may well
be differences in argument structure and alignment, not only between different
types of derived three-participant constructions but also between derived and
un-derived three-participant constructions (see e.g. Rose; Jansen; Russell et
al.; Haude, all this issue).
6.
Three-Participant Constructions - Summary and
Outlook
The previous sections discussed how the
encoding of three-participant events is conditioned by a variety of factors.
Among these, referential factors constitute the focus of attention of the
present collection of papers. However, these referential factors interact with
other factors, including the semantic (micro-)roles of different event types, as
expressed by individual lexical verbs belonging to specific verb classes. These
lexico-semantic factors are in their turn intertwined with formal factors such
as specific argument-marking strategies, and with functional factors such as
frequency, analogy, and transparency.
The discussion in the previous sections makes clear
that issues arising in studies on intransitive/monotransitive alignment and
argument realization are relevant for three-participant constructions as well.
At the same time, these issues need to be assessed independently. More
specifically, the data presented in this special issue - very briefly
summarized in the final section of this introduction - shows that
referential effects on argument realization in one- and two-participant
constructions of a particular language do not directly carry over to
three-participant constrictions in that
language.[6]
The possible mismatches
are of several types: the nature and number of the relevant referential factors
may differ; the relative ranking of referential factors and of individual
referential values may differ; the way in which referential factors are applied
may differ (i.e. the referential effect may be of the differential versus the
co-argument conditioned type); and - of course - the formal effects
may differ.
Finally, it is worth pointing out that corpus-based
and experimental research, of the type carried out for English and Dutch, is
still restricted in endangered languages, for which both data base sizes and
speaker numbers are comparatively limited. Consequently, explanations based on
patterns of usage frequency and processing are in need of empirical support from
more and more diverse languages. The studies collected in this issue represent
very promising steps towards achieving this goal.
7. The
Papers Collected in This Issue
Françoise
Rose on Mojeño Trinitario
, an Arawakan
language of Bolivia
Moje-o Trinitario has co-argument
conditioned indexation in monotransititive constructions: the form used to index
A depends on whether P is a 3rd person or speech act participant
(1st or 2nd person). The paper compares three types of
three-participant constructions: underived 'give'-type
constructions, and two types of derived constructions: causatives and
applicatives. The first two types are shown to display an alternation between
neutral and indirective alignment determined by a person-hierarchy (SAP>3),
to the extent that only SAPs can be indexed on the verb. In addition, underived
and causative (but not applicative) constructions both provide evidence for
construction-specific alignment, each in a slightly different
way.
Joana
Jansen on Yakima Sahaptin, a dialect of the Sahaptin language spoken in the
Pacific Northwest of the United States
The structure of monotransitive
constructions in Yakima Sahaptin is heavily dependent on referential factors.
Both case marking of A and indexation of A and P are co-argument conditioned,
involving the factors of person and topicality. Animacy determines differential
case marking of P. The paper describes the effects of these referential factors
on the encoding of a range of three-participant constructions, involving three
underived verb classes and two derived constructions. Construction alternation,
in the form of competition between T and G for object status is found with
'give'-type verbs and with causatives. Three-participant
constructions involving other verb classes display either indirective or
secundative alignment.
Lena
Russell, Inge Genee, Eva van Lier, and Fernando Zúñiga on
Blackfoot, an Algonquian language spoken in Southern Alberta (Canada) and
Northern Montana (United States)
Algonquian languages are renowned for
their strongly referentially determined grammatical systems, involving such
factors as animacy, person, and topicality. Blackfoot represents a special case
in that specificity plays a crucial role in argument encoding as well. In
monotransitive constructions, verbal inflection - in the form of person
indexation and direct-inverse marking - is co-argument conditioned. The
authors discuss the effects of referential factors on different types of derived
and underived three-participant constructions. In addition, they identify
interaction with lexical factors: some verbs allow both indirective and
secundative alignment, and in this case construction choice depends on the
animacy of R.
Katharina
Haude on Movima, an isolate spoken in Amazonian Bolivia
Movima has a system that resembles
Blackfoot to the extent that monotransitive constructions are fully determined
by the relative referential properties of A and P, involving direct-inverse
marking on the verb, although there is no agreement. The relevant referential
factors involve person and topicality. Three-participant constructions can be
indirectively or secundatively aligned: either T or G is treated like P and
enters into the monotransitive direct-inverse marking system; the remaining
participant is always encoded as an oblique. Interestingly, construction choice
is fully lexically determined, and some verbs with seemingly very similar
semantics exhibit different alignment patterns.
Alexandre
Françoise on Araki, an Oceanic language spoken on an island of the same
name in Vanuatu
In this language, the marking of
monotransitive P is determined by the referential factors of humanness and
anaphoricity, independently of the properties of A. In three-participant
constructions, we find co-argument conditioned marking, depending on the
relative properties of T and G and involving the additional referential factor
of person. Moreover, we see a strong lexical factor at work, in the sense that
the referentially determined construction alternation is specific to a single,
three-member verb class, expressing prototypical transfer of physical or mental
possession.
Stefan
Schnell on Vera'a, an Oceanic language of North
Vanuatu
Vera-a also has differential P
marking, but the details of the relevant referential factors and values and the
formal effects are different from those attested in Araki. This differential
P-marking is carried over to T, and the flagging of G is also differential,
depending on animacy. Within this indirective alignment pattern, however, there
is variation in the order of T and G, influenced by the relative anaphoricity
and topicality of these participants. Finally, it is shown that indirective
three-participant constructions are associated with caused motion; for the
expression of caused possession Vera-a uses an adnominal construction that
draws on two distinct types of possessive constructions.
Diana
Schackow on Yakkha, a Kiranti language spoken in East
Nepal
Yakkha has co-argument conditioned
agreement, and differential A-marking based on the factor of person. Concerning
three-participant constructions, three verb classes are distinguished, each
displaying a distinct basic alignment of case and agreement marking. One class
in fact displays an alignment mismatch in the sense that case is neutral, but
case agreement marking is secundative. Furthermore, there are several types of
referentially determined construction alternations, which affect case and/or
agreement marking. While the referential factors of person and animacy play a
role in co-argument conditioned alternations, only animacy is relevant for
differential case-marking of G. Finally, the Yakkha data show that individual
verbs may select specific referential types of (non-agent) participants,
allowing for instance animate Gs only or inanimate Ts only. When a verb
disallows a referentially high-ranking T, such an argument may still be
introduced into the construction by means of verb serialization.
Marian
Klamer and Antoinette Schapper on Papuan languages spoken on the islands of
Timor, Alor, and Pantar
This paper adds a historical dimension
to the present issue: it sketches the diachronic development of
-give- constructions in ten languages, starting from the observation
that each of these languages synchronically employs two or three different
construction types. While all of these constructions are secundatively aligned
in terms of verbal indexation, they differ as to the encoding of T, which is
either bare or flagged in different ways. These flagging strategies are shown to
stem from serial verb constructions of several types, and they display different
degrees of grammaticalization.
Chiyo
Nishida on Mexican Spanish
This paper uses frequency data from a
written corpus, investigating an alternation pattern involving three-participant
constructions with a prepositionally marked G argument, which may or may not be
doubly expressed by means of a clitic. The results suggest that clitic doubling
is restricted to referentially high-ranking G arguments, while constructions
without doubling do not exhibit this restriction. In addition, more fine-grained
distributional patterns can be discerned for individual lexical
verbs.
References
Anagnostopoulou, Elena. 2003. The syntax of
ditransitives: evidence from clitics. Berlin:
Mouton de Gruyter.
Aissen, Judith. 2003. Differential object
marking: Iconicity vs. economy. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory
21.435-483.
Bickel, Balthasar. 2008. On the scope of the
referential hierarchy in the typology of grammatical relations. Case and
Grammatical Relations: Studies in Honor of
Bernard Comrie, ed. by Greville G. Corbett and
Michael Noonan, 191-210. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
-----. 2010. Grammatical relations typology.
The Oxford Handbook of
Language Typology, ed. by Jae Jung Song,
399-444. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bickel, Balthasar and Johanna Nichols. 2009.
Case marking and alignment. The handbook of
case, ed. by Andrej Malchukov and Andrew
Spencer, 304-321. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bickel, Balthasar and Alena
Witzlack-Makarevich. 2008. Referential scales and case
alignment: reviewing the typological evidence.
Scales, ed. by Andrej Malchukov and Marc Richards, 1-37. Leipzig: Institut
für Linguistik.
Bickel Balthasar, Alena Witzlack-Makarevich,
and Taras Zakharako. 2010. Alignment across
the lexicon. Paper presented at Syntax of the
World's Languages IV, Lyon, 23-26 September 2010.
Bonet, E. 1994. The Person-Case constraint: A
morphological approach. The Morpho-syntax
Connection. MIT Working Papers in Linguistics
22, ed. by Heidi Harley and Colin Philips, 33-52.
Bossong, Georg. 1985. Empirische
Universalienforschung: differentielle Objektmarkierung
in neuiranischen Sprachen. T-bingen:
Narr.
Bresnan, Joan, Anna Cueni, Tatiana Nikitina,
and Harald Baayen. 2007. Predicting the dative
alternation. Cognitive Foundations of
interpretation, ed. by Gerlof Bouma, Irene Kr-mer, and Joost Zwarts, 69-94.
Amsterdam: Royal Netherlands Academy of Science.
Colleman, Timothy. 2006. De Nederlandse
datief-alternantie (The Dutch dative alternation). PhD-Thesis, Ghent
Universiy.
-----. 2009. Verb disposition in argument
structure alternations: a corpus study
of the dative alternation in Dutch. Language
Sciences 31.593-611. doi:10.1016/j.langsci.2008.01.001
Comrie, Bernard. 1989. Language Universals and
Linguistic Typology. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 2nd revised
edition.
Croft, William. 1990. Typology and universals.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
DeLancey, Scott. 1981. An interpretation of
split ergativity and related patterns. Language
57.626-657. doi:10.2307/414343
Dixon, Robert M. W. 1994. Ergativity.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Goldberg, Adele 1995. Constructions: A
Construction Grammar approach to argument
structure. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Gries, Stephan and Anatol Stefanowitsch. 2004.
Extending collostructional analysis.
International journal of Corpus Linguistics
9.97-129. doi:10.1075/ijcl.9.1.06gri
Haspelmath, Martin. 2004. Explaining the
Ditransitive Person-Role Constraint: a usage-based
account.
Constructions
2.1-49.
-----. 2005. Argument marking in ditransitive
alignment types.
Linguistic
Discovery 3/1.1-21 doi:10.1349/ps1.1537-0852.a.280
-----. 2007. Ditransitive alignment splits and
inverse alignment. Functions of
Language 14/1.197-102. doi:10.1075/fol.14.1.06has
-----. 2011. On S, A, P, T and R as comparative
concepts for alignment
typology. Linguistic typology
15/3.535-567. doi:10.1515/lity.2011.035
Heine, Bernd & Christa K-nig. 2010. On
the linear order of ditransitive objects. Language
Sciences 32/1.87-131. doi:10.1016/j.langsci.2008.07.002
de Hoop, Helen & Peter de Swart (eds.)
2009. Differential subject marking (Studies in
Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 72).
Springer.
Kittilä, Seppo. 2006. The woman showed the
baby to her sister. On humanness-driven
ambiguity in ditransitives. Case, valency and
transitivity, ed. by Leonid Kulikov, Andrej Malchukov and Peter de Swart,
291-308. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
-----. 2008. Animacy effects on differential
Goal marking. Linguistic Typology 12.
245-268. doi:10.1515/lity.2008.038
Levin, Beth. 1993. English verbs and
alternations: A preliminary investigation. Chicago:
University of Chicago
Press.
Malchukov, Andrej. 2008. Animacy and
asymmetries in differential case marking. Lingua
118.203-221. doi:10.1016/j.lingua.2007.02.005
Malchukov, Andrej, Martin Haspelmath and
Bernard Comrie. 2010. Ditransitive
constructions: a typological overview. Studies
in ditransitive constructions: A comparative handbook, ed. by Andrej Malchukov,
Martin Haspelmath and Bernard Comrie, 1-64. Berlin: Mouton de
Gruyter.
Nichols, Johanna 1992. Linguistic diversity in
space and time. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Ormazabal, Javier and Juan Romero. 2007. The
Object agreement constraint. Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory
25/2.315-347. doi:10.1007/s11049-006-9010-9
Perlmutter, David, M. 1971. Deep and surface
structure constraints in syntax. New York:
Holt Rinehart and Winston.
Peterson, David A. 2007. Applicative
constructions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rappaport-Hovav, Malka and Beth Levin. 2008.
The English dative alternation: The case for
verb sensitivity. Journal of Linguistics
44.129-167. doi:10.1017/s0022226707004975
Siewierska, Anna 2003. Person agreement and the
determination of alignment. Transactions
of the Philological Society
101/2.339-370.
-----. 2004. Person. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Siewierska, Anna and Dik Bakker. 2007. Bound
person forms in ditransitive clauses revisited.
Functions of Language
14/1.103-125. doi:10.1075/fol.14.1.07sie
Siewierska, Anna and Eva van Lier. 2012a.Ditransitive construction with two human non-agentive arguments. Faits de Langues 39.141-156 (special issue on La saillance, ed. by Kathaina Haude and Annie Montaut).
-----. 2012b. Introduce: encoding a non-prototypical three-participant event across Europe. To appear in Argument Structure in Flux:
The Naples/Capri Papers, ed. by Elly van Gelderen, Michaela Cennamo and Johanna
Bar-dal. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Silverstein, Michael. 1976. Hierarchy of
features and ergativity. In Grammatical Categories
in Australian Languages, ed. Dixon, Robert M.
W., 112-171. New Jersey: Humanities Press.
de Swart, Peter. 2007. Cross-linguistic
variation in object marking. Doctoral Dissertation, Radboud
University.
de Swart, Peter, Geertje van Bergen and Eva van
Lier. 2011. Lexical preferences in Dutch
ditransitives. Poster presented at AMLAP 2011,
Paris, 1-3 September 2011.
Wasow, Thomas. 2002. Postverbal behavior.
Stanford: CSLI publications.
Witzlack-Makarevich, Alena. 2011. Typological
Variation in Grammatical Relations. Ph D dissertation, University of
Leipzig.
Witzlack-Makarevich, Alena, Taras Zakarkho,
Lennart Bierkandt, and Balthasar Bickel.
2011. Decomposing hierarchical alignment:
participant scenarios as conditions on alignment. Paper presented at SLE44,
Logro-o, 8-11 September 2011.
Zúñiga, Fernando. 2006. Deixis
and Alignment: Inverse Systems in Indigenous Languages of
the Americas. Amsterdam: John
Benjamins.
Author's Contact Information:
Eva van Lier
Department of Linguistics
University of Amsterdam
Spuistraat 210
1012 VT Smsterdam, Netherlands
E.H.vanLier@uva.nl
[1]
These hierarchies have been proposed in e.g. Croft 1990, Dixon 1994, Aissen
2003, Siewierska 2004, de Swart 2007.
[2]
The term
co-argument conditioned alignment is proposed by
Witzlack-Makarevich et al. (2011).
[3]
See Haspelmath (2011) for a discussion of different types of approaches to the
terms S, A, P/O and G/R as used in descriptive and comparative research. As
mentioned, I follow the 'Bickelian' approach
here.
[4]
I skip here the various formal explanations that have been offered for the
Ditransitive Person Role Constraint; Haspelmath (2004) provides an overview of
these.
[5]
One such 'deviant' pattern relates to the ordering of the T and G
with respect to each other. Further cross-linguistic evidence for referential
effects on constituent order in three-participant constructions can be found in
Siewierska & Bakker(2007), Heine & König (2010), and Schnell (this
issue).
[6]
cf. Haspelmath (2005), who finds no correlation between monotransitive and
ditransitive alignment.
|