The Argument-Adjunct Scale:
Applied Nominal and Locative Phrases in Xhosa
Alexander Andrason
Stellenbosch University
This paper examines the categorial status of applied elements in Xhosa
with respect to their argumenthood or adjuncthood. By analyzing the response of
nominal and locative applied elements to various criteria and diagnostics and
by adopting the hypothesis of a scalar distinction between arguments and
adjuncts, the author proposes the following: The applied noun phrase approaches
the prototype of argumenthood to a great degree, while the applied locative
phrase is placed in the intermediate zone of the continuum, closer to the pole
of adjuncthood than the is the case of the nominal variant. The article provides further evidence
that (a) an approximate and relative scale is more realistic than an exact and
numerical scale, and that (b) the valency status of a verb is, to
an extent, conditioned by the dependent elements, thus failing to be directly
and/or exclusively projected by the verbal head.
1. Introduction
Applicatives
(i.e. applicative verb constructions) and applied noun and locative phrases have
extensively been studied for Xhosa and other Nguni languages (e.g. Zulu and
Ndebele). They have also been widely analyzed in the Bantu language
family (cf. Section 3). In Nguni languages, applicative verbal stems are
derived by means of the morpheme -el-
which increases the valency pattern of an underlying verb (intransitive or transitive) by an additional
position. In Xhosa, the standard view is that the nominal or locative elements that fill that extra position created by the applicative
morpheme are arguments (Du Plessis & Visser 1992, 1998). The present paper
analyzes the status of such applied elements from the theoretical standpoint
recently proposed in a collection of papers that formed a thematic issue of Language Discovery 12(2). This approach treats
the categories of argument(hood) and adjunct(hood) as compositional and
constructional prototypes, and the relationship between them as gradient and
fuzzy (Arka 2014, Creissels 2014, Forker 2014, Haspelmath 2014 and Wichmann
2014; see also Aarst 2008; for details see Section 2 below).
The study will
be structured in the following manner: I will begin with a detailed
presentation of the theoretical framework in Section 2. In Section 3, I will
introduce evidence. In particular, I will analyze the response of the applied
nominal and locative phrases to the criteria and diagnostics proposed by the theory. In Section 4, I will discuss the findings in light
of the theoretical framework, determining the categorial status of the two types
of applied elements. Section 4 will conclude the paper.
2. Framework
The issue of
distinguishing arguments from adjuncts is complex. It has troubled scholars for
the last fifty years and remains unresolved (Wichmann 2014:1). The problem
starts with the very definition of the two concepts and the criteria that
enable one to classify something as argument or adjunct.
In general, for
defining an item as argument or adjunct, two major criteria have been proposed:
the semantic and the syntactic criterion. The semantic criterion asserts that
certain expressions are viewed as central to the predicate, whereas others are
peripheral. The former are referred to as arguments. The
latter are adjuncts (Forker 2014:27). The semantic criterion implies that
arguments are necessary to saturate the predicate. They are profoundly involved
in the event conveyed by the verb to the degree that if not present, that event
cannot be conceived. In other words, arguments are actors that matter to the
situation expressed by the predicate, constituting crucial elements of the
process to which it refers. They are entailed by the lexical verb and not by other contextual elements. In contrast, adjuncts are not necessary to complete
the predicate and to conceive the situation it expresses. They fail to be
entailed by the lexical verb. Rather, they matter to the situation as a whole
and constitute background’s props (Tesnière 1959, Van Valin 2001:93, Farrell 2005:31, Creissels 2014:42, Forker 2014:27, Haspelmath
2014:3-4, Schikowski, Paudyal & Bickel forthcoming). The syntactic
criterion concerns a specific verb and not the situation it portrays. It
examines whether the syntax of a language requires that verb to be filled out
(or accompanied) by an element. If it
does so, that element is an argument. In a contrasting case, it is an adjunct
(Forker 2014).
Semantic
argumenthood or adjuncthood (i.e. being an argument or adjunct) is sometimes
viewed as (relatively) universal and therefore suitable for comparative and
crosslinguistic studies. This probably stems from the fact that in typological
studies, meaning (or function) is viewed as “more basic” than form (or
structure). To
be exact, in typology, onomasiological analysis (which studies strategies that can express a given concept)
precedes semasiological analysis (which studies concepts that can be associated
with a given form). In typology, the “meaning-first” approach is preferred over the “form-first” approach as the first step in research
(Croft 2003:13-14). The
approach to arguments and adjuncts is sometimes similar. Since argumenthood and
adjuncthood can be expressed in a variety of manners (mostly language specific), to constitute
comparative concepts they should be rather defined semantically than
syntactically, i.e. independently from their structural formulations (Creissels 2014).
Whatever the
exact view is on where the analysis should begin, evidence shows that semantic
valency and syntactic valency cannot be equated (Haspelmath 2014:4). There is
no straightforward correspondence between the semantic concept of argument as
an essential participant and its formal expression or syntactic necessity. To
put it simply, semantically essential participants do not have to be expressed
in syntactic terms (Van Valin 2001:93, Haspelmath 2013:4, Creissels
2014:42-43). Inversely, elements that are not semantically essential may appear
as syntactically obligatory (Haspelmath 2013:4).
Even though
semantic argumenthood and adjuncthood may be more basic and more easily
applicable to comparative studies than their syntactic equivalents, they are
not flawless. Relying on decisions made by descriptive
linguists and on native speakers’ intuition, the semantic definitions of the two concepts are imprecise, heavily psychological, and testable with difficulties. More objective and empirically testable methods
are necessary for the detection of arguments and adjuncts in specific
languages. These methods are referred to as (syntactic) criteria or
diagnostics. They too, however, have limitations (Engel 1977, Vater 1978,
Somers 1984). Most importantly, although sometimes one condition is singled
out, scholars disagree which criterion or diagnostic
is decisive (both necessary and sufficient) and applicable to all languages.
Therefore, a list of possible criteria and diagnostics is proposed (Forker
2014:28). But even the list itself is debatable and varies depending on the
researcher’s views.
As already
mentioned, in this study, I will adopt a list that can be inferred from a
thematic issue of Linguistic Discovery 12(2)
dedicated to arguments and adjuncts and their distinction. This list consists of
major criteria and specific diagnostics. As criteria, the following are
distinguished: obligatoriness, latency, co-occurrence restrictions, grammatical
relations, iterability and learnability/predictability (Forker 2014, Haspelmath
2014). First, arguments are necessitated by the predicate, while adjuncts are optional (Koenig et al. 2003:72, Forker 2014:29). As explained above, this obligatoriness can be
semantic or syntactic with no one-to-one correlation. Only the latter will be
relevant to this study as the former is, in my view, too elusive. To recall, syntactic arguments are required by the syntax of a language, while adjuncts are not (Forker 2014:29).
Second, arguments necessitate a definite reading when unexpressed, whereas
adjuncts also admit an indefinite reading. That is, arguments can be left out
only if they are accessible in the context. Indefinite and inaccessible
arguments cannot be omitted (ibid.). Third, prototypical arguments are restricted to
specific predicates. They cannot be used with any predicate. In contrast, adjuncts
are not restricted to any particular predicates,
being compatible with many, if not all, verbs (Forker 2014:30). Fourth, arguments are terms (i.e. subject, direct
object, indirect object
etc.), while adjuncts
are non-terms (i.e. oblique;
ibid). Fifth, arguments are non-iterable, while adjuncts
are iterable. That is, adjunct may be added
“freely” to any clause, whereas
arguments cannot (Forker
2014:31). Sixth, from a
language acquisition perspective, arguments are verb-specific and must be learned
separately for each verb. The use of adjuncts independent of specific predicates (Haspelmath 2014:5). As diagnostic techniques, the following postulated (Forker
2014:32): First, arguments are morphologically coded in a fixed manner, while adjuncts admit a greater variety or flexibility as far as their encoding is concerned. Second,
arguments exhibit morphological case marking, while adjuncts tend to be marked by means of adpositions. Third, arguments are marked for grammatical cases, while
adjuncts are rather marked for semantic cases.
Fourth, in head-marking languages, arguments are
indexed on verbs, while adjuncts are not. Fifth, arguments have the potential to access all valency-changing processes
(e.g. passivization), while adjuncts
do not. Sixth, arguments usually
occupy a position that is closer to the verb, while adjuncts may be placed further
from the verb (for instance, at the clause boundary). The position of arguments also tends to be more restricted in the clause,
while the position
of adjuncts is more flexible (Forker 2014:32-38). Lastly, since adjuncts are sometimes defined as relations, while arguments are not, in some languages, adjuncts can be introduced by overt relational predicates (Schaefer
& Egbokhare 2014).
The discussion above shows that neither criteria nor diagnostics constitute a unified set. That is, both the set of criteria
and the set of diagnostics contain elements of a differential and, to
an extent, unrelated nature. This means that valency (and thus argumenthood and
adjuncthood) is a composite concept consisting of and/or being derivable from a
number of finer-grain or more atomic concepts (Forker 2014).
The concepts of argumenthood and adjuncthood are not only composite, but also scalar (Aarst 2008, Forker 2014, Creissels 2014, Arka 2014). This means that the distinction is not binary, i.e. in terms of dichotomy, but rather gradient (Langacker 1987, Croft 2001, Keizer 2004, Aarts
2008, Wichmann 2014). This gradient nature implies that there is no clear-cut
borderline separating arguments and adjuncts. On the contrary, there is a large
sphere – a transition phase – where constructions or items mix the properties
of the two categories. Although this continuum is fuzzy (Forker 2014), it may
be fragmentized into sub-categories if
necessary (Arka 2014).
The
argument-adjunct scale (or continuum) is developed by postulating two ideal
prototypes – an ideal argument (or a state of canonical argumenthood) and an
ideal adjunct (a state of canonical adjuncthood). These prototypes are ideal
categories in the sense that they fulfill all possible criteria, which may play
a role in the definition of arguments or adjuncts discussed above (Arka 2014).
The strategy consists of observing how a realistic construction complies with the criteria and/or how it performs on the diagnostic tests. Subsequently, in light
of these observations, the construction is matched with a point on the
argument-adjunct cline. It can match one of the postulated prototypes (the extreme poles of the scale) or it can be located in the intermediary sections of
the continuum, thus mixing certain properties of the two categories and
constituting a less prototypical instantiation of the ideal categories of
argument or adjunct (Forker 2014:27).
As there are a number of criteria and diagnostics, the cline seems to be inherently fuzzy and the location of a construction
on it not easily calculable. However, both the scale and the position of an
item on it can be rendered more workable, namely more discrete and more
precise. This is sometimes achieved
by introducing the so-called argument-index analysis. This index specifies the extent to which an element approaches the prototype of argument or adjunct
in exact numerical terms, ranging from 1.00 (prototypical argument) to 0.00
(prototypical adjuncts; Arka 2014:61). Nevertheless, the actual progression from one
end to the other is gradual and no discrete borderline exists in any fragment of the continuum. Generally, items regarded
in concrete languages as arguments would score high on the scale (e.g. close to
1.00). Items defined as obliques would score less, being placed in intermediate
values (e.g. 0.50). Lastly, items regarded as adjuncts would receive the lowest
mark (e.g. close to 0.00; Arka 2014:62).
One should also note that in a specific language each occurrence of an item may receive a different value on the scale.
That is, the score is construction- and context-specific (Aarts 2008:186). Accordingly, general concepts (e.g. subject, direct object, locative etc.), even if
restricted to one language, can be located in different zone of the scale.
This, in turn, implies that each language-specific category can correspond to a
section of the cline (not only to one point on it) if analyzed in its totality.
This makes the gradient and fuzzy nature of argument-adjunct distinction even
more evident (Arka 2014:77).
Applicatives, which constitute the topic of this paper, epitomize the scalar nature of the argumenthood-adjuncthood distinction
and this distinction’s complexity. In Xhosa and related African languages, applicatives are related to two
principal concepts: beneficiary and location/direction. Applicatives commonly license (new) items with
the semantic role of beneficiary. Crosslinguistically, the status of
beneficiaries is unstable. They may exhibit behavior that places them closer to arguments or closer to adjuncts on the continuum (Creissels 2014). That is, in some languages, beneficiaries are
encoded in a manner analogous to adjuncts, whereas in others they may be encoded like
arguments. Applicatives also involve locative or directional
ideas, as they commonly refer to: (a) places where the event referred to by the
verb takes place, (b) places from which it originates (e.g. sources); and c)
places to or towards which it heads (e.g. goals). Locatives, like
beneficiaries, can travel along the argumenthood-adjuncthood scale, exhibiting the status closer to arguments or closer to adjuncts,
depending on a language and/or construction in which they appear. Thematic, individuated, specific locatives can be attracted towards the
pole of argumenthood, while non-thematic, poorly individuated, and non-specific
locatives tend to exhibit a more adjunct-like character (Arka 2014:69, 71).
3. Evidence
In this section,
I will present properties of the applicatives in Xhosa, focusing on those
traits that are relevant for the determination of the position of an applied slot on the argument-adjunct scale. As already mentioned, in Xhosa, the applicative affix -el- increases the verb’s valency by one non-subject position, which
can be filled out by a N(oun) P(hrase; see Section 3.1) or by a L(ocative)
P(hrase; see Section 3.2). For each type, I will first study the response of
the applied slot to the six criteria relevant for the determination of their
categorial status as arguments or adjuncts (Forker 2014). Next, I will examine
the nominal and locative applied slots in respect to the six diagnostic
techniques.
I will treat the classification proposed by Du Plessis & Visser (1992, 1998) as my point of departure or a type of a null hypothesis. According to these scholars, the categorial status of
the nominal and locative applied slots is identical, both being defined as
arguments. The evidence provided in this section, and its subsequent discussion
in section 4, will demonstrate that this classification may be enhanced and
rendered more nuanced.
3.1 Applied
noun phrases (NP)
The presence of
an applied NP is usually obligatory. That is, the syntax of Xhosa requires that the predicate extended by the affix
-el- be accompanied by an applied
noun in order to be complete (Du Plessis & Visser 1992, 1998). This holds
true both for the applicatives derived from intransitive verbs (1a) and the applicatives derived from transitive verbs (1b). Inversely, the absence of an applied
noun phrase renders the sentence incomplete (1c-d).
(1)
|
a.
|
Le
|
nkwenkwe
|
i-balekela
|
ibhola
|
|
|
CL9.DEM
|
CL9.boy
|
CL9-run.APPL
|
CL5.ball
|
|
|
‘This boy runs for the ball.’
|
|
b.
|
Ndi-phekela
|
amakhwenkwe
|
ukutya
|
|
|
I-cook.APPL
|
CL6.boy
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘I cook food for the boys.’
|
|
c.
|
*Le
|
nkwenkwe
|
i-balekela
|
[-]
|
|
|
CL9.DEM
|
CL9.boy
|
CL9-run.APPL
|
|
|
|
intended: ‘This boy runs for the cup.’
|
|
d.
|
*Ndi-phekela
|
[-]
|
ukutya
|
|
|
I-cook.APPL
|
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
intended: ‘I cook food.’
|
In agreement
with the latency condition, it is impossible to leave the argument
syntactically unexpressed if it is inaccessible in the context and/or if its
interpretation is indefinite. In fact, in the case of the applied NP in Xhosa,
even definite and accessible arguments cannot be omitted.
As far as
co-occurrence restrictions are concerned, applied NPs in Xhosa are more
restricted than canonical adjuncts (which can virtually occur with any
predicate) but less restricted than canonical arguments (which are limited to
specific predicates). To be exact,
applied noun phrases – tautologically – only appear with applicatives.
Furthermore, their presence is constrained by the fact that for certain verbs
it is a locative and not a mere noun phrase that is (or should be) used (see Section
3.2). Overall, the presence of applied nouns is conditioned by the meaning of
the verb. Such a behavior approximates them to arguments (cf. Forker 2014:30).
In Xhosa,
nominal elements that fill out the place created by the applicative affix can
be regarded as terms. In general, in applicative verbs formed from intransitive
verbs, applied NPs function as direct objects. For applicative verbs formed
from transitive verbs, applied NPs approximate indirect objects. As the
notions of a direct and an indirect object are themselves complex, I will give a detailed explanation of the categorization of applied NPs as terms.
In the case of
applicatives derived from intransitive roots, applied NPs behave in a manner
analogous to direct objects in Xhosa (cf. Du Plessis 2010:118). That is, their
syntactic properties (such as word order, pronominalization, object agreement
and passivization) are fully analogous to those of direct objects. To be exact,
for such verbs, applied NPs are the only, and thus primary objects. The
applied NP immediately follows the verb (2a-b) and if moved to other
non-canonical positions usually triggers object agreement on the verb (3a-b).
The applied NP may also be replaced by a pronominal affixed agglutinated to the
verb. Both in the case of agreement and pronominalization, the applied NP uses
the same pronominal forms as direct objects (4a-b). (Observe that Xhosa uses the
same pronominal affixes for direct and indirect objects.) In passive constructions, the applied NP
is promoted to the subject position and triggers
a subject concord
with the verb (5a-b). The following examples illustrate these specific properties of applied NPs by comparing
them with direct objects in non-applicative
constructions:
(2)
|
a.
|
Ndi-vuyela
|
umfundi
|
|
|
I-be.happy.APPL
|
CL1.student
|
|
|
‘I am happy for the student.’
|
|
b.
|
Ndi-bona
|
umfundi
|
|
|
I-see
|
CL1.student
|
|
|
‘I see a student.’
|
(3)
|
a.
|
Umfundi
|
ndi-yam-vuyela
|
|
|
CL1.student
|
I-CL1-be.happy.APPL
|
|
|
‘I am happy for the student.’
|
|
b.
|
Umfundi
|
ndi-yam-bona
|
|
|
CL1.student
|
I-CL1-see
|
|
|
‘I see a student.’
|
(4)
|
a.
|
Ndi-yam-vuyela
|
|
|
I-CL1-be.happy.APPL
|
|
|
‘I am happy for him.’
|
|
b
|
Ndi-yam-bona
|
|
|
I-CL1-see
|
|
|
‘I see him.’
|
(5)
|
a.
|
Umfundi
|
u-vuyelwa
|
ngabantu
|
|
|
CL1.student
|
CL1-be.happy.APPL.PASS
|
by.CL2.person
|
|
|
‘People
are happy for the student.’
|
|
b.
|
Umfundi
|
u-yabonwa
|
|
|
CL1.student
|
CL1-see.PASS
|
|
|
‘The student is being seen.’
|
In applicatives
derived from transitive verbs, the applied NP generally behaves in a manner
typical of indirect objects in Xhosa (Plessis & Visser 1992:30, 1998:86).
In many aspects this behavior suggests that the applied-object is the primary
object of the applicative verb. First, as far as word order is concerned, the
applied NP precedes the non-applied direct object. This complies with the word
order of non-applicative ditransitive verbs (e.g. nika ‘to give’), in which indirect objects of a non-applicative
verb precedes the direct object:
(6)
|
a.
|
Ndi-bhalela
|
umfundi
|
ileta
|
|
|
I-write.APPL
|
CL2.student
|
CL5.letter
|
|
|
‘I write a
letter to a student.’
|
|
b.
|
Ndi-nika
|
umfundi
|
ileta
|
|
|
I-give
|
CL2.student
|
CL5.letter
|
|
|
‘I give a letter to a student.’
|
Second, the
applied NP (i.e. the NP licensed by an applied verb/affix) may be
pronominalized and/or trigger object agreement on the verb by employing the
same set of pronouns as the indirect object
of non-applied predicates. These pronominal affixes are, however, formally
indistinguishable from direct object affixes:
(7)
|
a.
|
Ndi-m-bhalela
|
ileta
|
|
|
I-CL1-write.APPL
|
CL5.letter
|
|
|
‘I write him a letter.’
|
|
b.
|
Ndi-m-nika
|
ileta
|
|
|
I-CL1-give
|
CL5.letter
|
|
|
‘I give him a letter.’
|
Third, as far
as passivization is concerned, the behavior of an applied NP found in
applicative constructions which are derived from transitive predicates,
complies with the behavior exhibited by indirect objects of ditransitive
(non-applicative) verbs in Xhosa. However, from a crosslinguistic perspective,
the behavior of applied NPs is less exemplary of indirect objects, rather
approximating such noun phrases to direct and/or primary objects. To begin
with, the applied NP can be to the subject position, thus yielding the subject concord on the verb. In such cases, the
direct non-applied object (i.e. the object of the basic verb stem) remains in
the object position (see examples (8a-b) for applicatives and (8c-d) for non-applicatives).
(8)
|
a.
|
Ndi-kuphekela
|
abantwana
|
ukutya
|
|
|
I-cook.APPL
|
CL2.child
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘I cook food for the children.’
|
|
b.
|
Abantwana
|
ba-yaku-phekelwa
|
ukutya
|
|
|
CL2.child
|
CL2-CL15-cook.APPL.PASS
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘The
food is being cooked for the children.’
|
|
|
lit. ‘The children are being cook the food.’
|
|
c.
|
Ndi-nika
|
abantwana
|
ukutya
|
|
|
I-give
|
CL2.child
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘I give food to the children’
|
|
d.
|
Abantwana
|
ba-yaku-nikwa
|
ukutya
|
|
|
CL2.child
|
CL2-CL15-give.PASS
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘The
children are being given food.’
|
In applicative
passive constructions, if one of the two NPs is pronominalized by means of
verbal affixes, only the applied NP may be promoted to the subject position
(9a). In contrast, the direct object of an applicative verb cannot be promoted to the subject role if the applied NP is pronominalized on the verb (9b; cf.
Dyubeni 1993:96-97, 99-100). This may suggest a higher status of the applied NP
than that of the non-applied direct object and thus its interpretation as a primary object (compare a similar observation for Tswana noted by Creissels 2014). However, one should
bear in mind that the same phenomenon is found with non-applicative
ditransitive verbs (9c-d).
(9)
|
a.
|
Abantwana
|
ba-yaku-phekelwa (Dyubeni 1993:96)
|
|
|
CL2.child
|
CL2-CL15-cook.APPL.PASS
|
|
|
‘It is cooked for the children.’
|
|
b
|
*Ukutya
|
ku-yaba-phekelwa (ibid.:97)
|
|
|
CL15.food
|
CL15-CL2-cook.APPL.PASS
|
|
|
intended:
‘Food is cooked for them.’
|
|
c.
|
Abantwana
|
ba-yaku-nikwa
|
|
|
CL2.child
|
CL2-CL15-give.PASS
|
|
|
‘The children are being given it.’
|
|
d.
|
*Ukutya
|
ku-yaba-nikwa
|
|
|
CL15.food
|
CL15-CL2-give.PASS
|
|
|
‘The food is being given to them.’
|
If the
non-applied object is to be promoted to the subject position and the applied NP
realized pronominally in passives in the object position, the applied NP must be
encoded by means of an absolute pronoun. Inversely, if the applied NP is encoded by means of an absolute pronoun, the non-applied (direct) object may appear in the subject
position (10a). If the applied NP functions as a subject in the passive, the
non-applied direct object may also appear as an absolute pronoun in the object
position (10b):
(10)
|
a.
|
Ukutya
|
ku-phekelwa
|
bona (Dyubeni 1993:97)
|
|
|
CL15.food
|
CL15-cook.APPL.PASS
|
CL2.ABS
|
|
|
‘Food is cooked for them.’
|
|
b.
|
Abantwana
|
ba-phekelwa
|
kona (ibid.)
|
|
|
CL2.child
|
CL2-cook.APPL.PASS
|
CL15.ABS
|
|
|
‘It is cooked for the children.’
|
As far as the
last criterion (i.e. iteration) is concerned, the applied NP cannot be iterated
and the predicate freely expanded by a series of different applied NPs. This is contrary to canonical
adjuncts in Xhosa, which may be added freely to the predicate and accumulated
in a clause. Therefore, example (11) is generally ungrammatical. Of course,
this may be rendered acceptable if the conjunction na ‘and’ is used (that is abafundi nootitshala nabazali). However, in such a case, one would deal with coordination and
not with iteration.
(11)
|
*Ndi-phekela
|
abafundi
|
ootitshala
|
abazali
|
ukutya
|
|
I-cook.APPL
|
CL2.student
|
CL2a.teacher
|
CL2.parent
|
CL15.food
|
|
intended: *‘I cook food for
students, teachers, parents.’
|
As for the
diagnostics, the following should be noted: the morphosyntactic encoding of the
applied NPs is uniform. It does not allow for alternative variations, which
complies with the encoding characteristic of arguments in Xhosa. To be exact, all applied NPs are encoded in the same manner as non-applied arguments in Xhosa, lacking any specific morphological marking – they merely display the appropriate class-prefix.
The applied NP
is never marked by means of adpositions, contrary to adjuncts that in Xhosa regularly are introduced by adpositions agglutinated to the noun. This approximates the applied NP to the category of a morphological case rather
than an adpositional case, even though nouns are not morphologically inflected
for case in Xhosa.
Most semantic
properties of the applied NP link it to a grammatical case (namely the dative)
rather than to a semantic or spatial case. However, as will be evident from the
subsequent discussion, this categorization is not discrete. Overall, the
applied NP may assume a variety
of semantic on its own properties and on discourse For underlying intransitive verbs, the applied NP offers three
principal roles: (broad)
beneficiary (12a), goal (purpose) (12b) and cause (12c).
(12)
|
a.
|
Le
|
ndoda
|
i-buyela
|
inkosi (Du Plessis & Visser 1998:82)
|
|
|
CL9.DEM
|
CL9.man
|
CL9-return.APPL
|
CL9.chief
|
|
|
‘This man returns for (the benefit / on behalf of) the
chief.’
|
|
b.
|
Le
|
nkwenkwe
|
i-balekela
|
indebe (Du Plessis & Visser 1998:82)
|
|
|
CL9.DEM
|
CL9.man
|
CL9-run.APPL
|
CL9.cup
|
|
|
‘This boy runs for (the purpose of) the cup.’
|
|
c.
|
Ingozi
|
i-hlele
|
imvula (Du Plessis & Visser 1998:82)
|
|
|
CL9.accident
|
CL9-happened.APPL
|
CL9.rain
|
|
|
‘The accident happened because (for the reason) of the
rain.’
|
For underlying transitive verbs, the semantic roles of the applied object are comparable to those
typical of underlying intransitive verbs. That is, with animate noun phrases,
the most common reading is
beneficiary (13a) while for inanimate noun phrases it is goal (purpose; 13b)
and cause (14c; Plessis & Visser 1998:86-90).
(13)
|
a.
|
USipho
|
u-qhubela
|
uyise
|
imoto (Plessis & Visser
1998:86)
|
|
|
CL1a.Sipho
|
CL1a-drive.APPL
|
CL.1his-father
|
CL9.car
|
|
|
‘Sipho drives the car for his
father.’
|
|
b.
|
Umtshakazi
|
u-khethela
|
umtshato
|
ilokhwe
(ibid.:88)
|
|
|
CL1.bride
|
CL1-choose.APPL
|
CL3.wedding
|
CL9.dress
|
|
|
‘The bride chooses a dress for
the wedding.’
|
|
c.
|
U-m-khetela
|
ntoni
|
unyana (ibid.:90)
|
|
|
you-CL1a-select.APPL
|
what
|
CL1a.son
|
|
|
‘Why are you selecting the son.’
|
Although the meanings of beneficiary, goal (purpose) and cause predominate, applied NPs can also bear other roles, namely
source (14a), direction (14b), and, less commonly, theme (14c-d) and recipient
(15e; Du Plessis & Visser 1992:28-29, 1998:82-84).
(14)
|
a.
|
U-bhacela
|
umqeshi
|
|
|
CL1-flee.APPL
|
CL1.employer
|
|
|
‘He flees from the employer.’
|
|
b.
|
U-ngxamele
|
uloliwe
|
|
|
CL1-hurry.APPL
|
CL11.train
|
|
|
‘He hurried up to the train.’
|
|
c.
|
U-khalazela
|
umqeshi
|
|
|
CL1-complain.APPL
|
CL1.employer
|
|
|
‘He complains about the
employer.’
|
|
d.
|
U-cacele
|
ukutya
|
|
|
CL1-like.APPL
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘He likes the food.’
|
|
e.
|
U-mangalela
|
isikolo
|
|
|
CL1-complain.APPL
|
CL7.school
|
|
|
‘He complained to the school.’
|
If one imagines
a prototypical grammatical and a prototypical semantic case as two opposite
extremes of a continuum, the range of semantic roles offered by the applied NP
locates it in a zone between a grammatical and semantic case, close to the area
occupied by a dative case. The semantic role of recipient, which can be
sometimes borne by the applied NP is regularly associated with the dative. The roles such as beneficiary and goal (purpose) – the most typical
of the applied NP – also constitute, crosslinguistically, common meaning
extensions of the dative. It should
however be noted that out of all the “dative” roles, it is beneficiary and goal
roles (less grammatical but more semantic) that are regular of the applied NP,
while the recipient (more grammatical and less semantic) is significantly less
frequent. Additionally, the role of a theme, likewise
sporadically available with the applied NP, locates it even closer to
grammatical cases as this role is typical of direct objects encoded by the
accusative. Nevertheless, more spatial roles such as direction, location as
well as source attract the applied NP toward the other, more semantic pole
of case-continuum.
As already
mentioned, the applied NP may be indexed on the verb. First, the applied object can be replaced by means of pronominal affixes in the same manner as the direct and/or indirect object of transitive verbs (see also example 8a above):
(15)
|
a.
|
Ndi-phekela
|
abantwana
|
ukutya (Dyubeni 1993:60)
|
|
|
I-cook.APPL
|
CL2.child
|
Cl15.food
|
|
|
‘I cook food for children.’
|
|
b.
|
Ndi-ba-phekela
|
ukutya (ibid.)
|
|
|
I-CL2-cook.APPL
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘I cook food for them.’
|
Second, the applied
NP can be co-indexed with a pronominal affix agglutinated to the verb,
triggering object agreement. This occurs if the applied object is to be specified (16a) or if it is moved out of its canonical position (16b).
(16)
|
a.
|
Ndi-ba-phekele
|
abantwana
|
ukutya
|
|
|
I-CL2-cook.APPL.PERF
|
CL2.children
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘I cooked food for the
children.’
|
|
b.
|
Abantwana
|
ndi-ba-phekela
|
ukutya
|
|
|
CL2.child
|
I-CL2-cook.APPL
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘I cook food for the children.’
|
If two NPs –
the applied and the non-applied – are to be pronominalized at the same time, one of them must be expressed as the absolute pronoun. That is, when the applied NP is realized as a verbal affix, the non-applied object surfaces as an absolute
pronoun (17a). Inversely, if the applied NP appears as an absolute pronoun, the
non-applied object may be incorporated with the
verb as a pronominal affix (17b).
(17)
|
a.
|
Ndi-ba-phekela
|
kona (Dyubeni 1993:61)
|
|
|
I-CL2-cook.APPL
|
CL15.ABS
|
|
|
‘I cook it for them.’
|
|
b.
|
Ndi-ku-phekela
|
bona (ibid.)
|
|
|
I-CL15-cook.APPL
|
CL2.ABS
|
|
|
‘I cook it for them.’
|
Applied NPs
allow for all valency-changing processes in Xhosa. Most importantly, they can
be passivized. The properties of applied NPs in passives have
been discussed previously in this section. To recapitulate, applied NPs – both in applicatives derived from intransitive (18a) and transitive verbs (18c) – can be promoted to the
subject position in a passive construction (Dyubeni 1993:96). In such cases,
the verb may exhibit subject agreement with the applied NP promoted to the
subject role (18b and 18d). Thus, the applied NP exhibits the same behavior as the most prototypical arguments in Xhosa, namely direct and/or indirect objects of non-applied verbs.
(18)
|
a
|
Ndi-cacele
|
ukutya
|
|
|
I-like.APPL.PERF
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘I like food.’
|
|
b.
|
Ukutya
|
ku-cacelwe
|
|
|
CL15.food
|
CL15-like.APPL.PASS.PERF
|
|
|
‘The food is liked.’
|
|
c.
|
Ndi-phekela
|
abantwana
|
ukutya
|
|
|
I-cook.APPL
|
CL2.child
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘I am cooking food for the
children.’
|
|
d.
|
Abantwana
|
ba-yaphekelwa
|
ukutya (Djubeni 1993:96)
|
|
|
CL2.child
|
CL2-cook.APPL.PASS
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘Food is (being) cooked for the
children.’
|
As explained above, if two internal NPs are to be expressed pronominally, only the applied NP can
be used as the subject in a passive construction. That is, in multiple object
constructions, applied objects are, syntactically, primary objects (cf.
Creissels 2014:51). The applied NP can always be promoted to the role of the
subject in a passive construction (19a). In contrast, the non-applied NP
sometimes cannot, as the presence of an applied index on the verb makes it
impossible to promote the non-applied object to the position of the subject (19b); see analogous behavior in Tswana observed by
Creissels 2014:51, mentioned previously). One should however bear in mind that this behavior is not limited to the applied object but also pertains to the indirect object of non-applied verbs (19c).
(19)
|
a.
|
Abantwana
|
ba-yaku-phekelwa (Dyubeni 1993:96)
|
|
|
CL2.child
|
CL2-CL15-cook.APPL.PASS
|
|
|
‘It is cooked for the children.’
|
|
b.
|
*Ukutya
|
ku-yaba-phekelwa (ibid.:97)
|
|
|
CL15.food
|
CL15-CL2-cook.APPL.PASS
|
|
|
‘Food is cooked for them.’
|
|
c.
|
*Ukutya
|
ku-yaba-nikwa
|
|
|
CL15.food
|
CL15-CL2-give.PASS
|
|
|
‘The food is given to them.’
|
It has also
been mentioned that the applied NPs regularly appear in the position closest to
the verb. That is, applied NPs immediately follow the inflected verb, either in applicatives derived from intransitive verbs (where they constitute the only
nominal slot), or in applicatives derived from transitive verbs (where there
is another nominal slot – the direct object). This means that if two NPs are used, the applied one is placed closer to the verb than the non-applied one (20a). This behavior is
typical of all indirect objects in Xhosa. However, in some cases, this word
order can be altered and the applied NP can be located after the non-applied object.
This happens especially if the applied NP is animate and the non-applied (direct) object is inanimate so that the interpretation of
their roles (as beneficiary and theme respectively) is evident irrespective of
their positon (20b).
(20)
|
a.
|
Ndi-phekela
|
isikolo
|
ukutya (Dyubeni 1993:62)
|
|
|
I-cook.APPL
|
CL7.school
|
CL15.food
|
|
|
‘I cook food for the school.’
|
|
b.
|
Ndi-phekela
|
ukutya
|
umtwana
|
|
|
I-cook.APPL
|
CL15.food
|
CL1.child
|
|
|
‘I cook food for a child.’
|
The position of applied objects is relatively restricted. As mentioned above, an applied objects tend to appear immediately after the verb. If moved to the pre-verbal position (fronting or
left dislocation) the pronominal agreement typically appears on the verb (cf.
21; see also example 17b above). These properties are consistent with the behavior
of non-applied nominal arguments in Xhosa in general. In contrast, the
position of adjuncts in Xhosa is significantly less restricted (Du Plessis & Visser 1998). Adjuncts can appear at the beginning or at the end of the clause, and their movement does
not generally require agreement on the verb.
(21)
|
Umfundi
|
ndi-m-bhalela
|
ileta
|
|
CL1.student
|
I-CL1-write.APPL
|
CL5.letter
|
|
‘To the
student I write a letter.’
|
3.2 Applied locative
phrases (LP)
The applied LP is the other possible slot licensed by the applicative suffix in Xhosa (Du Plessis & Visser 1992:133). As
mentioned previously, the LP is a
noun accompanied by a locative marker: either an affix e- and e-…-ini (and its
allomorphs) or an agglutinative preposition ku- (see further below in this section). The LP is obligatory in these types of applicative verbs and, thus,
necessary for such predicates to be completed. In this manner, locatives that in non-applied structures constitute peripheral and omissible items, are promoted to the status of the core elements
of a predicate (Plessis & Visser 1992:51, 1998:154).
(22)
|
a.
|
Ndi-fikele
|
e-sititshi-ni
|
|
|
I-arrive.APPL.PERF
|
LOC-CL7.station-LOC
|
|
|
‘I arrived at the station.’
|
|
b.
|
*Ndi-fikele
|
|
|
I-arrive.APPL.PERF
|
|
|
intended: ‘I (have) arrived.’
|
The Applied LPs
are more restricted than canonical adjuncts in Xhosa. Canonical adjuncts – which
can also exhibit a locative marking – may virtually occur with any predicate. In
contrast, applied locatives, by definition and tautologically, can only be
found with applicative verbs. In fact, they are restricted to a certain number
of such applicative predicates as
many of applicatives require the use of an NP rather than an LP (cf. section 3.1). Overall, the
presence of an applied LP is
licensed by the meaning of the verb and must be learned individually, as is
exemplary of arguments.
Applied LPs are
not canonical terms as they cannot be classified as prototypical direct or indirect objects. As far as word order is concerned, in applicatives derived from intransitive verbs, the
applied LP immediately follows the
verb. However, in applicatives derived from transitive verbs, the applied LP regularly follows the nominal object
(cf. 23a), contrary to indirect object of non-applicative verbs and the applied
NP discussed in Section 3.1. Furthermore, applied LPs are rarely indexed on
the verb, neither by pronominalization (23b) nor by object agreement (23c; see
further below in this section). Nevertheless, they are characteristics that also link the applied
LP to grammatical terms. In passive constructions, the applied LP (24a
and 25a) may be promoted to the subject position, thus triggering subject
concord with the verb (24b and 25b). This is typical of direct and indirect
objects as well as applied NPs (cf. section 3.1 above).
(23)
|
a.
|
Ndi-bhalela
|
ileta
|
ku-Sipho
|
|
|
I-write.APPL
|
CL5.letter
|
LOC-CL1a.Sipho
|
|
|
‘I write the letter to Sipho.’
|
|
b.
|
*Ndi-ku-bhalela
|
ileta
|
|
|
I-CL15-write.APPL
|
CL5.letter
|
|
|
intended: ‘I write him a
letter.’
|
|
c.
|
*Ndi-ku-bhalela
|
ileta
|
ku-Sipho
|
|
|
I-CL15-write.APPL
|
CL5.letter
|
CL1a.Sipho
|
|
|
intended: ‘I write the letter to
the child.’
|
(24)
|
a.
|
Abantu
|
ba-buyela
|
e-doloph-ini
|
|
|
CL2.person
|
CL2-return.APPL
|
LOC-CL9.town-LOC
|
|
|
‘People return to the town.’
|
|
b.
|
E-doloph-ini
|
ku-buyelwa
|
ngabantu
|
|
|
LOC-CL9.town-LOC
|
CL15-return.APPL.PASS
|
by.CL2.person
|
|
|
‘People return to the town.’
|
(25)
|
a.
|
Ndi-bhalela
|
ileta
|
ku-mfundi
|
|
|
I-write.APPL
|
CL5.letter
|
LOC-CL1.student
|
|
|
I write a letter to the
student.’
|
|
b.
|
Ku-mfundi
|
ku-bhalelwa
|
ileta
|
|
|
LOC-CL1.student
|
CL15-write.APPL.PASS
|
CL5.letter
|
|
|
‘A letter is being written to
the student.’
|
Lastly, as far
as the criteria are concerned, the applied locatives seem to allow iteration (26a). That is, the clauses that contain
an applicative verb and an LP may be
expanded by more than one LP in a non-coordinating manner so that more than one locative expression is accumulated in the
clause. However, the subsequent LPs are in fact not the applied LPs sensu stricto, but rather “ordinary” locative adjuncts, which as explained may be added freely. Thus, the sentence
in (26a) can be further expanded by other adjuncts, for instance by eMzantsi Afrika ngoJune ‘in South Africa
in June’. This, in turn, would mean that applied locatives cannot be iterated
(26b). This confusion, which exists with inanimate locatives, seems to be absent with animate
applied locatives. This type of an applied locative cannot be reiterated,
unless by means of coordination. If an inanimate locative is added to an
animate applied LP, the former will be reinterpreted as an adjunct (26c)
(26)
|
a.
|
Abantu
|
ba-buyela
|
e-doloph-ini
|
e-Mpuma-Koloni
|
|
|
CL2.person
|
CL2-return.APPL
|
LOC-CL9.town-LOC
|
LOC-Eastern.Cape
|
|
|
‘People return to the town in
the Eastern Cape.’
|
|
b.
|
*U-sebenzela
|
ku-nyana, |
e-mfazi-ni
|
|
|
CL1-work.APPL
|
LOC-CL1a.son
|
LOC-CL1.wife-LOC
|
|
|
intended: ‘He works for his son,
his wife, the school.’
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
c.
|
U-sebenzela
|
ku-nyana,
|
e-sikolw-eni
|
|
|
CL1-work.APPL
|
LOC-CL1a.son
|
LOC-CL7.school-LOC
|
|
|
‘He works for his son in the
school.’
|
As for the
diagnostics, the morphosyntactic encoding of applied LPs is not uniform.
The applied LP exhibits three main
variants: e-…-ini and its allomorphs (edolophini ‘in/to the town’), e- (egaraji ‘in/to the garage’) and ku- (kumfundi ‘to the student’). However, the range of locative affixes usually found
with applied LPs is more limited than is the case of all types of adjuncts
indicating location. Apart from the encoding mentioned above, locative adjuncts
can be introduced by various locative prefixes, prepositions or prepositional phrases with more specific semantic
values: nga ‘near to’, ngaphandle kwa ‘outside’, ngaphakati kwa ‘inside’, phezu kwa ‘on (top) of’, etc. While these are common with locative adjuncts, they do not normallyoccur with applied locatives, especially if a non-locative/directional role is profiled (cf. further below in this section).
Applied LPs
are marked by means of typical locative prefixes which have an adpositional
character even though they are agglutinated to the noun. These marking grosso modo complies with the encoding characteristic of locative adjuncts in Xhosa. Inversely, applied LPs differ from typical arguments, which do not possess any marking of a prepositional type, being only
marked for the noun class prefix.
Applied LPs
exhibit semantic properties that link them to semantic cases rather than to a genuine grammatical case (Du Plessis 2010). The most common semantic roles conveyed by the applied LP are exemplary of
semantic cases (direction, locative) and more semantic roles of grammatical
cases (beneficiary, goal). However, instances of roles typical of grammatical
cases are also found. To be exact, with underlying intransitive verbs, the
applicative affix usually introduces a locative slot with the role of direction
(27a), location (27b) or exclusive location (27c; also referred to as implicit
contrast). All of them are typical of spatial cases (Plessis & Visser 1998:154-158).
(27)
|
a.
|
Le
|
ntombi
|
i-buyela
|
e-doloph-ini (Plessis & Visser 1998:156)
|
|
|
CL9.DEM
|
CL9.girl
|
CL9-return.APPL
|
LOC-CL9.town-LOC
|
|
|
‘This girl is returning to the
town.’
|
|
b.
|
Uloliwe
|
wa-fikela
|
e-sitishi-ni (ibid.:158)
|
|
|
CL11.train
|
CL11. PAST-arrive.APPL
|
LOC-CL7.station-LOC
|
|
|
‘The train arrived at the station’
|
|
c.
|
Abantu
|
ba-lilela
|
e-caw-eni (ibid.:158)
|
|
|
CL2.person
|
CL2-cry.APPL
|
LOC-CL9.church-LOC
|
|
|
‘The people cry only in the church.’
|
A similar range
of semantic roles can be attested with underlying transitive verbs: direction
(28a), location and exclusive location (28b; Plessis & Visser 1992:55-57,
1998:160-164).
(28)
|
a.
|
U-qhubela
|
imoto
|
e-sikolw-eni
|
|
|
CL1-drive.APPL
|
CL9.car
|
LOC-CL7.school-LOC
|
|
|
‘He drives the car to the
school.’
|
|
b.
|
U-sikela
|
inyama
|
e-tafile-ni
|
|
|
CL1-cut.APPL
|
CL9.meat
|
LOC-CL9.table-LOC
|
|
|
‘He cuts meat only on the
table.’
|
Apart from the
semantic roles specified above, which are typical of semantic cases rather than grammatical cases, applied locatives can also express less spatial nuances: purpose/goal (29a),
beneficiary (29b), recipient (29c-d) and theme (29e; Du Plessis & Visser
1992:51-54, 1998:154, 158). All of these roles relate the applied LP to grammatical cases. The roles of goal,
beneficiary and recipient relate it to the dative, while the role of theme
relates it to the accusative. The non-spatial and more grammatical roles are
more common with animate locatives.
(29)
|
a.
|
Wa-vukela
|
e-bhasi-ni
|
|
|
CL1.PAST-wake.up.APPL
|
LOC-CL9.bus-LOC
|
|
|
‘He woke up to catch the bus.’
|
|
b.
|
U-sebenzela
|
ku-nyana
|
wakhe
|
|
|
CL1-work.APPL
|
LOC-CL1a.son
|
his
|
|
|
‘He works for his son.’
|
|
c.
|
U-mangalela
|
ku-nyana
|
wakhe
|
|
|
CL1-complain.APPL
|
LOC-CL1a.son
|
his
|
|
|
‘He complains to the son.’
|
|
d.
|
Umfundi
|
u-bhalela
|
ileta
|
ku-yise (Du Plessis & Visser 1992:57)
|
|
|
CL1.student
|
CL1-write.APPL
|
CL5.letter
|
LOC-CL1.his.father
|
|
|
‘The student writes a letter to
his father.’
|
|
e.
|
Indoda
|
i-krokrela
|
e-mfazi-ni (Du Plessis & Visser 1992:51)
|
|
|
CL9.man
|
CL9-be.suspicious
|
LOC-CL1.woman-LOC
|
|
|
‘He is suspicious of the woman.’
|
Contrary to
applied NPs, applied LPs are normally not indexed on the verb as pronominal
object affixes. Thus, they do not exhibit object agreement in case of movement
(30a) or for specification (30b) analogous to that found with applied NPs. However, when moved to the
initial position, the verb may take the pronominal subject affix (or the
agreement affix) of the locative ku class
(30c-d). As explained, this use of ku may
be understood not as the subject agreement with the locative ku class but rather as the existential
(indefinite) subject. This existential reading is evident in the case of
subject inversion where the applied LP follows
the verb and the subject (30e; Mtoba 1985, Visser 2005).follows
the verb and the subject (30e; Mtoba 1985, Visser 2005). All these properties are typical of locative
adjuncts rather than arguments in Xhosa.
(30)
|
a.
|
*E-ntombi-ni
|
ndi-ku-khenkethela
|
|
|
LOC-CL9.daughter-LOC
|
I-CL15-visit.APPL
|
|
|
intended:
‘The daughter’s place I am visiting.’
|
|
b.
|
*Umfundi
|
u-kui-hambela
|
e-ntombi-nii
|
|
|
CL1.student
|
CL1-CL15-visit.APPL
|
LOC-girl-LOC
|
|
|
intended:
‘Student visits the girl.’
|
|
c.
|
E-cawe-ni
|
ku-lilela
|
abantu
|
|
|
LOC-CL9.church-LOC
|
CL15-cry.APPL
|
CL2.people
|
|
|
‘People are crying in the church.’
|
|
d.
|
E-sitratwe-ni
|
ku-gcwele
|
iimoto
|
|
|
LOC-CL7.street-LOC
|
CL15-be.plentiful.APPL.PERF
|
CL10.car
|
|
|
‘The
street is full of cars.’
|
|
e.
|
Ku-lilela
|
abantu
|
e-cawe-ni
|
|
|
CL15-cry.APPL
|
CL2.people
|
LOC-CL9.church-LOC
|
|
|
‘People are crying in the
church.’
|
As mentioned
above, an applied LP allows for certain valency-changing processes in Xhosa,
such as passivization. In passives,
applied LPs can be promoted to the subject position and trigger subject
agreement with the verb. This property is found with applicatives derived from underlying intransitive (31a) and transitive (31b) verbs. To be exact, the applied LP can occur
as the subject in a passive construction, while the direct object (if it is
expressed in the clause built around an active applicative verb) remains in the
object position (see again 31b).
(31)
|
a.
|
E-doloph-ini
|
ku-yabuyelwa
|
ngabantu
|
|
|
LOC-CL9.town-LOC
|
CL15-return.APPL.PASS
|
by.CL2.person
|
|
|
‘People return to the town.’
|
|
b.
|
E-khaye-ni
|
lethu
|
ku-cingelwa
|
imali
|
|
|
LOC-CL5.house-LOC
|
ours
|
CL15-think.APPL.PASS
|
CL9.money
|
|
|
‘In our house there is concern
about money.’
|
The applied LP regularly appears in the position further from to the verb than any other nominal slots. If the applicative is
derived from an underlying transitive verb, the applied LP is placed after the direct objects (32a). If the applicative
construction is derived from an underlying ditransitive verb, the applied LP
appears after the two objects, that is further to the right than the direct and
indirect objects (the latter encoded by the applied NP; 32b). Of course, if the
applicative structure is derived from an intransitive verb, the applied LP
appears closest to the verb, as no other object or nominal slot intervenes.
However, although applied locatives occupy a position that is more distant
from the verb than is the case of prototypical arguments, they also occur
closer to the verb than prototypical adjuncts. This means that adjuncts usually
follow the applied LP (32c).
(32)
|
a.
|
Ndi-memela
|
abafundi
|
e-khaye-ni
|
lam
|
|
|
I-invite.APPL
|
CL2.student
|
LOC-CL5.house-LOC
|
mine
|
|
|
‘I invite students to my home.’
|
|
b.
|
Indoda
|
i-hlawulela
|
uThemba
|
inkomo
|
e-gqirhe-ni
|
|
|
CL9.man
|
CL9-pay.APPL
|
CL1a.Themba
|
CL9.cow
|
LOC-witchdoctor-LOC
|
|
|
‘The man pays
a cow to the witchdoctor on behalf of Themba.’
|
|
c.
|
Nda-fikela
|
e-Kapa
|
ngoMqibelo
|
18.June
|
ngo-1994
|
|
|
I.PAST-arrive
|
LOC-Cape.Town
|
on.Monday
|
18.June
|
in.1994
|
|
|
‘I arrived in Cape Town on
Monday 18 June 1994.’
|
With a few
underlying ditransitive verbs (e.g. ukunika ‘to give’ and ukuthuma ‘to
send’), the use of the applicative affix and locative marking makes it possible
to shift the indirect object encoded by the applied NP from the immediate post-verbal position (33a) to the position after the direct object (33b), thus moving the recipient further from
the predicate:
(33)
|
a.
|
Ndi-thumela
|
abantwana
|
imali
|
|
|
I-send.APPL
|
CL2.child
|
CL9.money
|
|
|
‘I am sending the children
money’
|
|
b.
|
Ndi-thumela
|
imali
|
e-bantwane-ni
|
|
|
I-send.APPL
|
CL9.money
|
LOC-children-LOC
|
|
|
‘I am sending money to the children.’
|
The position of
applied locatives is less restricted than the position of objects (including
the applied NP), although it is more restricted than the position of temporal,
instrumental and locative adjuncts. As explained above, although the LP usually
appears after any other object, it can be moved to the pre-verbal position
(fronting or left dislocation). In such a case, the movement fails to trigger
object agreement (34a) and optionally may yield locative subject agreement,
which is similar to and sometimes indistinguishable from the existential ku (34b).
(34)
|
a.
|
E-doloph-ini
|
abantu
|
ba-yabuyela
|
|
|
LOC-CL9.town-LOC
|
CL2.person
|
CL2-return.APPL
|
|
|
‘People return to the town.’
|
|
b.
|
E-doloph-ini
|
ku-buyela
|
abantu
|
|
|
LOC-CL9.town-LOC
|
CL15-return.APPL
|
CL2.person
|
|
|
‘People return to the town.’
|
4. Discussion
The evidence
indicates that, with respect to almost all the criteria and diagnostics, the
applied NP performs as if it were an argument. First, the applied NP responds
to the six criteria in a manner similar to canonical arguments. That is, the applied NP fulfills the criterion of syntactic
obligatoriness. As is representative of arguments, the presence of the applied
NP is required by syntax – the applied NP being necessary for the verb to be complete.
The applied NP is obligatory to the extent that it cannot be left unexpressed,
even though it is contextually accessible and/or definite. With respect to the criterion of co-occurrence,
the applied NP exhibits an intermediate character. That is, the presence of an
applied NP is more restricted than the presence of canonical adjuncts, albeit
possibly less restricted than canonical arguments. As for the criterion of
grammatical relations, the applied NP is a term (similar to a primary object
and a direct/indirect object) which is typical of arguments. Furthermore,
applied NPs cannot be iterated and, to a degree, must be learned, at least to a
greater degree than prototypical adjuncts. Thus, as far as the criteria of
iterability and learnability are concerned, the applied NP approximates
canonical arguments.
Second, as far
as diagnostics are concerned, on most tests the applied NP performs as a
canonical argument. The encoding of the applied NP is uniform. Although there
is no morphological case in Xhosa, the marking of the applied NP may be
understood as basically morphological (like any prototypical argument in Xhosa)
and never adpositional (which is typical of adjuncts). The applied NP is commonly indexed on the verb, which is also typical of arguments. This indexation surfaces as both pronominalization and object agreement. The applied NP may likewise
undergo valency changing processes, especially passivization, thus behaving as
an exemplary argument. Lastly, as far as its position in the clause is
concerned, the applied NP exhibits typical properties of arguments. It is located closest to the verb, and in fact closer than any other argument. It is also relatively restricted, especially if compared to adjuncts. In contrast, with respect to the diagnostic of grammatical or semantic
case, the applied NP exhibits properties of a mixed
nature. Overall, the semantic properties locate the applied NP closer to the
grammatical case than to the semantic case. To be exact, the applied NP most commonly behaves as a variant of the dative case. However, in its less prototypical roles, the
applied NP may travel in both directions on the case continuum, that is towards
a more grammatical case (recipient and theme) or towards a more semantic case (locative).
The behavior of
the applied LP is more erratic. The applied LP may respond to the criteria and
perform on the diagnosing tests as if it were an argument, an adjunct or an
intermediate category. First, the six criteria jointly suggest an intermediary
status for the applied LP on the
continuum of argumenthood and adjuncthood. On the one hand, responding to
certain criteria, the applied LP behaves
in a manner exemplary of arguments. The applied LP is obligatory in an
applicative verb, thus behaving as an argument. The omission of an applied LP is never allowed, including if the LP
is definite and accessible in the context. Accordingly, indefinite and
inaccessible applied LPs can never be left unexpressed, which is consistent with the latency criterion. With respect to the criterion of co-occurrence, the applied LP is
also more restricted than canonical adjuncts in Xhosa and usually must be
learned. On the other hand, the remaining two criteria locate the applied LP in
an intermediate zone of the argument-adjunct scale. As far as the question of
grammatical relations is concerned, the applied LP is not a genuine term. It may be viewed as relatively remote
from the categories of primary/secondary objects and direct/indirect objects. The applied LP also tolerates
superficial iteration, although what seems to be an iterated applied LP is in fact a new, non-applied locative
adjunct. This may yield fuzzy cases.
As far as the diagnostics are concerned, the applied LP most often responds in a manner that is not typical of arguments. Rather, the applied LP performs as if it were an adjunct-like
category or a mixed category. To be precise, the encoding of the applied LP is
not uniform, although it is more uniform than the encoding of adjuncts in general. The encoding seems to be closer to adpositional marking rather than to a
genuine case. The applied LP combines
features of a grammatical case and a semantic case. Nevertheless, the range of
theta-roles and in particular the roles that are the most prototypical of the
applied LP (i.e. locative and
direction) approximate it closer to the semantic case, or at least to a highly semantic side of the dative case. In the manner characteristic of adjuncts, the applied LP is normally not indexed on the verb by
means of pronominal object affixes. However, the verb may take the pronominal
subject affix of the locative ku class.
As explained, this can also be viewed as the existential type of ku. In such a case, the applied LP would
fail to trigger any type of agreement. The position of the applied LP is less restricted than the position of
arguments in Xhosa. The applied LP is
also located at further distance from the verb than is the case of other
arguments in Xhosa. In contrast, one
property demonstrates that the applied LP may
also behave in an argument-like manner. To be exact, the applied LP allows for
certain valency-changing processes in Xhosa, especially for passivization where
it may possibly be promoted to the subject position and/or role.
Before
proposing a unified categorization of the applied NP and the applied LP, it
should be recalled that each criterion and diagnostic condition is scalar in
itself (cf. Forker 2014). That is, the criteria and diagnostics do not allow for binary
oppositions in terms of either fulfillment or non-fulfillment.
This implies that the applied NP and LP may
exhibit mixed characteristics with respect to every single criterion or diagnostic. As a result, the overall extent of argumenthood or adjuncthood of
the applied NP and LP (if both are
viewed as holistic categories) is not easily computable and their position on
the argument-adjunct continuum cannot be precisely
determined. In other words, the computation of all conditions into one digit or a point on the scale (or
into an exact range of digits or points) may not be possible. What can be
achieved, is the estimation and relative positioning of the applied NP and the
applied LP. That is, it is possible
to hypothesize a position that is approximate (i.e, numerically imprecise and fuzzy) and one that
locates the applied NP and the applied LP in relation to other NPs (typical
arguments) and LPs (typical adjuncts), as well as in relation to each other.
If taken in its
integrity, the applied NP is close to the argumenthood pole of the
argument-adjunct continuum. It seems
that only certain semantic properties pull the applied NP slightly away from
the extreme that symbolizes canonical argumenthood. Otherwise, the applied NP
behaves as an exemplary argument, sometimes even more prototypical than non-applied objects in applicative constructions. Accordingly, the applied NPs are
arguments to a comparable degree as any other non-applied arguments. Each group
offers a slightly distinct mixture of properties and compensates less canonical
behavior with respect to one condition by more canonical behavior with respect
to the others. The location of the applied LP
on the argument-adjunct scale is less clear-cut. As the applied LP exhibits both argument-like and
adjunct-like traits it is an intermediate category. Therefore, it may be viewed
as spanning the middle sections of the scale, being located between other more
canonical categories. On the one hand, it approximates canonical argumenthood
to a lesser degree than prototypical arguments in Xhosa, including the applied
NP. On the other hand, it behaves in a less
adjunct-like manner than the prototypical adjuncts. These mixed
properties of the applied LP make it
impossible to classify it either as an argument or as an adjunct. Rather, as
proposed above, the form attests to
an intermediate fuzzy state on the argument-adjunct scale.
Given the properties of the applied NP and the applied LP, it is possible to postulate the following relative cline of
argumenthood-adjuncthood in Xhosa: nominal non-applicative objects and applied
NPs > applied LPs > other locative and temporal expressions.
5. Conclusion
The present
study demonstrates that the applied NP and the applied LP have a dissimilar
status on the argument-adjunct scale. The applied NP approaches the pole of
argumenthood to a great degree, while the applied LP is placed in the
intermediate zone of the continuum. Accordingly, the applied LP occupies the
area relatively closer to the pole of adjuncthood than is the case with the
applied NP. In this manner, the
paper offers a more nuanced approach to applied NPs and LPs than the categorization proposed by Du Plessis & Visser
(1992, 1998) for whom both classes are arguments.
Furthermore,
the results of this article corroborate two other views proposed in the
thematic issue of Linguistic Discovery 12(2). First the data suggest that, even though the exact numerical scale (Arka 2014) may offer certain benefits (and may be the ultimate goal of future research) at this stage, it is not
realistic. The more realistic scale is approximate (non-numerical) and
relative (it positions categories of a language in relation to each other).
Accordingly, the solution proposed by Forker (2014) seems more workable. Second, given the contribution of the
semantic and morphosyntactic properties of the applied NP and LP to their argument-adjunct status, the
present study provides further arguments supporting the hypothesis according to
which the valency status of the verb is, to an extent, conditioned by the
dependent elements and not directly or exclusively projected by the verbal head
(Arka 2014).
Abbreviations
APPL: applied, ABS: absolute
pronoun, CL: class, LOC: locative, LP: locative phrase, NP: noun phrase, PASS: passive, PERF: perfect.
References
Aarst, Bas. 2007. Syntactic gradience. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Acedo-Matellán, Víctor. 2010. Arguments structure and
the syntax-morphology interface. A case study in Latin and other languages. PhD
dissertation, University of Barcelona.
Andrason, Alexander and Michael Karani. Forthcoming.
Dative applicative elements in Arusa (Maa) - A canonical approach to the argument-adjunct distinction. Stellenbosch Papers in Linguistic Plus
Arka, I. Wayan. 2014. Locative-related roles and the
argument-adjunct distinction in Balinese. Linguistic
Discovery 12/2.56-84.
Borer, Hagit. 2005. Structuring senses. Vol I: In name
only; Vol. II: The normal course of events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Borik, Olga and Jaume Mateu. 2014. Argument structure
in morphology and syntax: An introduction. Lingua
141.1-7.
Creissels, Denis 2014. Cross-linguistic variation in the
treatment of beneficiaries and the argument vs. adjunct distinction. Linguistic Discovery 12/2.41-55.
Croft, William. 2001. Radical construction grammar. New
York: Oxford University Press Croft,
William. 2003. Typology and universals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Du Plessis, Jacobus A. 1978. IsiXhosa 4. Goodwood: Oudiovista.
Du Plessis, Jacobus A. 2010. Comparative syntax: The
structure of the verb phrase in the African languages of South Africa (Bantu
languages). Stellenbosch: Stellenbosch University. http://scholar.sun.ac.za/handle/10019.1/3156
Du Plessis, Jacobus A. and Marianna Visser. 1992. Xhosa
syntax. Pretoria: Via Afrika.
Du Plessis, Jacobus A. and Marianna Visser. 1998.
Isintaksi yesixhosa. Stellenbosch communications in African languages 7.
Stellenbosch: Stellenbosch University.
Dyubeni, Nandipha Nomgcobo. 1993. A comparison between
applicative and non-applicative ditransitive verbs in Xhosa. M.A. dissertation,
Stellenbosch University.
Engel, Ulrich. 1977. Syntax der deutschen
Gegenwartssprache. Berlin: E. Schmidt.
Farrell, Patrick. 2005. Grammatical relations. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Forker, Diana. 2014. A canonical approach to the
argument / adjunct distinction. Linguistic
Discovery 12/2.27-40.
Harley, Heidi. 2011. A minimalist approach to argument
structure. The handbook of linguistic minimalism, ed. by Cedric Boeckx. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 427-448.
Haspelmath, Martin. 2014. Arguments and adjuncts as language-particular syntactic categories and as comparative concepts. Linguistic Discovery 12/2.3-11.
Hlungwani, Madala C. 1997. The applicative construction
in Xitsonga. M.A. dissertation, Stellenbosch University.
Jacobs, Joachim. 1994. Kontra Valenz. Trier:
Wissenschaftlicher Verlag Trier.
Keizer, Evelien. 2004. Postnominal PP complements and
modifiers; a cognitive distinction. English
language and linguistics 8/2.323-350.
Koenig, Jean-Pierre, Gail Mauner and Breton Bienvenue.
2003. Arguments for adjuncts. Cognition
89.67-103.
Langacker, Ronald. W. 1987. Foundations of cognitive
grammar, Vol I: Theoretical perspectives. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Letooane, M.B. 1992. The applicative, deverbative and
passive in South Sotho. M.A. dissertation, Stellenbosch University.
Levin, Beth and Malka Rappaport Hovav. 1995. Unaccusativity.
At the syntax-lexical semantics interface. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Makado, Adziliwi Samuel. 1996. The semantic
interpretation of the applicative in Venda. M.A. dissertation, Stellenbosch University.
Makhubu, Rosethal Lolie. 1997. The applicative
construction in Zulu. M.A. dissertation, Stellenbosch University.
Mkhabele, Zacharias Gregory G. 1999. The applicative
construction in Northern Sotho. M.A. dissertation, Stellenbosch University.
Motsei, Anastacia Sara. 1993. The semantic
interpretation of the applicative in Sesotho. M.A. dissertation, Stellenbosch
University.
Mtoba, H. P.1985. The subjectival concord ku in Xhosa. Stellenbosch studies in African languages
8/1.68-96.
Ozón, Gabriel.2007. Ditransitives in English: a
corpus-based study. PhD dissertation, UCL.
Rappaport Hovav, Malka and Beth Lewin. 1998.Building
verb meaning. The projection of arguments: Lexical and compositional factors,
ed. By Miriam Butt and Wilhelm Geuder. Stanford: CSLI Publications, 97-134.
Schaefer, Ronald P. and Francis O. Egbokhare. 2014.
Emai’s variable coding of adjuncts. Linguistic
Discovery 12/2.12-16.
Schikowski, Robert, Netra P. Paudyal, and Balthasar
Bickel. Forthcoming. Flexible valency classes in Chintang. Valency classes: a comparative handbook, ed. by Bernard Comrie and Andrej L. Malchukov. Berlin: De
Gruyter Mouton.
Somers, Harold L. 1984. On the validity of the
complement-adjunct distinction in valency grammar. Linguistics 22.507-530.
Tesnière, Lucien. 1959. Éléments de syntaxe
structurale. Paris: Klincksieck.
Van Valin, Robert D. 2001. An introduction to syntax.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Vater, Heinz. 1978. Distinguishing between complements
and adjuncts. Valence, Semantic Case, and Grammatical Relation, ed. by Werner
Abraham, 21-45. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Visser, Marianna. 2005. Xhosa. Encyclopedia of language
and linguistics, ed. by Keith Brown. Oxford: Elsevier, 705-716.
Wichmann, Søren. 2014. Arguments and adjuncts
cross-linguistically: A brief introduction. Linguistic
Discovery 12/2.1-2.