Relative clauses in Upper Necaxa Totonac:
Local, comparative, and diachronic
perspectives
David Beck
University
of Alberta
Relativization strategies
in the Totonacan family are largely undescribed, but detailed examination of
one of the languages in the group, Upper Necaxa Totonac, reveals the presence
of both externally- and internally-headed relative constructions. Also of note
is the presence of relativizers that mark the animacy (human/non-human) of the
head of the relative construction. This paper will show that, while
phylogenetic evidence clearly demonstrates the relativizers to be descended
diachronically from interrogative pronouns, they are best treated
synchronically as complementizers, an analysis that follows directly from the
presence of internally-headed relative constructions.
Totonacan
languages are spoken by approximately 240,000 people (INEGI 2010) living in an
area of east-central Mexico centred on northern Puebla State and including
adjacent parts of Hidalgo and Veracruz (see Figure 1; languages dealt with
directly in this paper are shown in red). The family is generally considered an
isolate; however, recent work has suggested links to Mixe-Zoque (Brown et al.
2011) and Chitimacha (Brown et al. 2014). Although the family has only recently
become the object of serious investigation and description, the focus has been
largely on its (admittedly spectacular) morphology; little has been written
about syntax, and even less about the structure of complex clauses. Relative
clauses in particular seem to have been given shortshrift—which is surprising,
given that from what we do know about them they seem to have some unusual
properties. Consider the example in (1) from Upper Necaxa Totonac, the language
for which we currently have the most data on relativization:

Figure 1: Location of Totonacan Languages
(1)
|
ʔawa̰čá̰n [tiː
taliːtatsḛ́ʔa ḭstsḭːká̰n]
|
|
ʔawa̰čá̰–n
|
[tiː
|
ta–liː–ta–tsḛʔ–a
|
ḭš–tsḭː–ka̰n
|
ØSUB]
|
|
boy–pl
|
hrel
|
3pl.sub–inst–dcs–hide–impf
|
3poss–mother–pl.po
|
__
|
|
‘those boys that hide behind their
mother(’s skirts)’
|
Here
we see a typical relative construction with an overt nominal, ʔawa̰čá̰n ‘boys’, being modified by a subordinate clause. The modified noun, or head of the relative clause, is external to the relative clause itself and is linked
to it by a relativizer—in this case, the animate (human) relativizer, tiː.
The head of the relative clause corresponds to the subject of the embedded
verb, which is elided or gapped, and the relative construction as a
whole can be considered subject-centred (i.e., the head of the clause is
co-referential with the subject of the subordinated verb). Upper Necaxa also
allows headless relative clauses (a.k.a. free relatives),
as in (2)
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(2)
|
[tiː
taliːtatsḛ́ʔa ḭstsḭːká̰n]
|
|
[tiː
|
ta–liː–ta–tsḛʔ–a
|
ḭš–tsḭː–ka̰n
|
ØSUB]
|
|
hrel
|
3pl.sub–inst–dcs–hide–impf
|
3poss–mother–pl.po
|
__
|
|
‘those that
hide behind their mother(’s skirts)’
|
In
a construction like this, the head of the relative clause is elided. The
subject in (2) is also gapped, but the relative remains subject-centred and the
referent of the construction as a whole is the subject of the embedded clause.
Such constructions in Upper Necaxa function quite happily as arguments of
verbs, like any other noun phrase, and are frequent in text.
In addition to the constructions in (1) and (2), Upper Necaxa also allows a third
possibility, shown in (3):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(3)
|
[tiː
taliːtatsḛ́ʔa ʔawa̰čá̰n ḭstsḭːká̰n]
|
|
[tiː
|
ta–liː–ta–tsḛʔ–a
|
ʔawa̰čá̰–n
|
ḭš–tsḭː–ka̰n]
|
|
hrel
|
3pl.sub–inst–dcs–hide–impf
|
boy–pl
|
3poss–mother–pl.po
|
|
‘those boys
that hide behind their mother(’s skirts)’
|
In (3), there is no overt
nominal head external to the subordinate clause. Instead, what appears to be
the head, ʔawa̰čá̰n ‘boys’, is found inside the
embedded clause, in this case immediately following the verb. This type of
construction is what is referred to as an internally-headed relative clause.
Cross-linguistically, internally-headed relative clauses are comparatively
rare, and they are even rarer in languages where, as in Upper Necaxa, they are
an infrequent, as opposed to a dominant, type of relative clause (Dryer 2013).
Another notable feature of the constructions in (1)–(3) is the element tiː,
which is used exclusively in relative clauses with animate (human) heads and
which has a counterpart, tuː, used with inanimates
(non-humans). While these are typically labeled “relativizers” in grammatical
descriptions of Totonacan languages, this term is actually (and probably
deliberately) vague in that it does not make it clear whether the relativizers
are to be understood as subordinators or
complementizers—linking elements in the clause
signalling/licensing subordination—or as relative pronouns, pronominal
elements standing in for the relativized argument of the embedded verb. The
fact that they encode animacy, a characteristic of nouns, suggests that they
might in fact be pronouns, as does the fact that in several of the languages in
the family, like Upper Necaxa, they are homophonous with the interrogative
pronouns, tiː ‘who?’ and tuː ‘what?’.
On the other hand, the relativizers are not, as canonical relative pronouns
are, inflected for case, nor is animacy a morphological or inflectional
category that manifests itself in other kinds of pronouns or in any other area
of the grammar. So, not only does Upper Necaxa have the cross-linguistically
unusual internally-headed type of relative clause, there is also an analytical
question at play here as to the exact nature of the relativizers that appear in
the relative constructions. As this paper will argue, these two phenomena are
linked, and the presence of the internally-headed construction in (3) can be used to show
that the relativizers are best not analyzed as relative pronouns in the usual
sense, but should instead be described as complementizers that, perhaps
unusually, agree with a semantic feature of the head of the relative constructions
that they introduce. This agreement, naturally, has a diachronic explanation
which is revealed by a comparative examination of relativization strategies
across the family.
The remainder of this paper will proceed as follows. Section 1 offers a brief
description of Upper Necaxa Totonac, focusing on the structure of the simple
clause, while Section 2 gives a detailed account of relativization in that language. In
Section 3,
I survey what is known about relativization in the rest of the family. The data
available is rather sketchy and there are only one or two dedicated
descriptions of relative clauses in other Totonacan languages; nevertheless, a
reasonably coherent picture of the family, and how the different branches of
Totonacan compare to each other and to Upper Necaxa, can be arrived at by
culling through texts and other sources. Section 4 will assess the implications of the
comparative picture for the diachronic development of the different
relativization strategies, and will propose an analysis of the relativizers
that supports the claim that they are best described as complementizers, at
least in Upper Necaxa and the other languages in the family that allow
internally-headed relative clauses.
Upper Necaxa
Totonac is a member of the Northern Totonac branch of the Totonacan language
family, spoken by 3,293 people (INEGI 2010) in the Necaxa River Valley in
northern Puebla State, Mexico. Like all Totonacan languages, Upper Necaxa can
be characterized as polysynthetic and primarily head-marking in the sense of
Nichols (1986). Verbs agree in person and number with their syntactic subjects;
transitive verbs also agree with their objects:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(4)
|
ḭkaːpaːɬ’áːɬ pá̰šnḭ
|
|
ḭk–kaː–paː–ɬ’aː–lḭ
|
pá̰šnḭ
|
|
1sg.sub–pl.obj–belly–cut.deeply–pfv
|
pig
|
|
‘I gutted
the pigs.’
|
In (4) we see the verb
paːɬ’aː ‘X cuts Y’s belly deeply’ bearing the first-person
singular subject prefix ḭk- and the plural object prefix, kaː-.
The object-noun itself, pá̰šnḭ ‘pig’ is unmarked for number,
which is an optional category for nouns, the preferred locus for number-marking
in the clause being on the verb. The categories of person and number of object
are marked separately, as in (5):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(5)
|
kaːtatṵ́ksnḭ
|
|
kaː–ta–tṵks–n–lḭ
|
|
pl.obj–3pl.sub–hit–2obj–pfv
|
|
‘They hit
you guys.’
|
Here,
the person of the object is encoded by the suffix, -n
‘second-person object’, while the plural number of the object is indicated by
the same prefix, kaː- ‘plural object’, that we saw in (4). Third-person
singular subjects, third-person objects, and the singular of objects are morphological
zeros (and in this paper will not be included in the glossing to avoid
cluttering the presentation).
In multivalent clauses, verbs can also agree in person with a second
object, if that object is first- or second-person:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(6)
|
wan tsṵma̰xáːt,
kintaːtá̰ kista̰ːmaškíːn
|
|
wan
|
tsṵma̰xáːt
|
kin–taːtá̰
|
kin–staː–maškíː–n
|
|
say
|
girl
|
1poss–father
|
1obj–sell–give–2obj
|
|
‘The girl
says, “My father sold me to you.” ’
|
This
example shows the trivalent verb sta̰ːmaškíː ‘X
sells Y to Z’, used in this context to refer to the exchange of a girl for a
dowry, agreeing with both a second-person and a first-person object. Upper
Necaxa is a primary-object language in the sense of Dryer (1986), making the
second-person recipient in this clause the primary object and the first-person
theme the secondary object.
Copular clauses can have either nominal (7) or adjectival (8) predicate
complements:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(7)
|
šantíɬ
šwanḭ́ː ḭšnaːná̰
Xiwán
|
|
šantíɬ
|
ḭš–wan–nḭː
|
ḭš–naːná̰
|
Xiwan
|
|
shaman
|
past–be–pf
|
3poss–grandmother
|
Juan
|
|
‘Juan’s
grandmother was a shaman.’
|
(8)
|
kiɬstayanka̰tṵnká̰
tsa̰má mačíːta̰
|
|
kiɬ–stayánka̰=tṵnká̰
|
tsa̰má
|
mačíːta̰
|
|
|
mouth–sharp=very
|
that
|
machete
|
|
|
‘That
machete is very sharp.’
|
The
copula is based on the verb wan ‘be’ and is immediately preceded by its
complement, as it is in other Totonacan languages. In the past tense, the
copula is invariably inflected in the past perfect, and in the future it takes
the future imperfective form nawán. It is generally omitted in the
present tense, as here in (8), but may optionally be realized in the present imperfective form, wan.
Also of note in (8) is the head-marked possessive construction ḭšnaːná̰ Xiwán
‘Juan’s grandmother’ in which the possessed NP is inflected for the person of
the possessor. The plurality of the possessor is optionally indicated by the
suffix -ka̰n (e.g., ḭšnaːna̰ká̰n Xiwán ʔeː Tséntṵ ‘Juan
and Rosendo’s grandmother’).
As in the rest of the family, constituent order in Upper Necaxa
clauses is extremely flexible and is governed primarily by
information/communicative structure (Vallduví 1992; Mel’čuk 2001). The
communicatively unmarked order is verb-initial, placing Upper Necaxa in Dryer’s
(1997) VS/VO category; however, essentially any order of verb and arguments is
possible for a given sentence in the appropriate context, as shown in (9):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(9)
|
ḭščiká̰n
kaːmaškíːɬ gobierno la̰ʔškamaniːníːn
|
SO
V S PO
|
|
ḭš–čik–ka̰n
|
kaː–maškíː–ɬ
|
gobierno
|
la̰ʔ–škamaníːn–niːn
|
|
3poss–house–pl.po
|
pl.obj–give–pfv
|
government
|
apl–pauper–pl
|
|
‘The
government gave the poor people their houses.’
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
kaːmaškíːɬ gobierno la̰ʔškamaniːníːn ḭščiká̰n
|
V S PO SO
|
|
gobierno
kaːmaškíːɬ la̰ʔškamaniːníːn ḭščiká̰n
|
S V PO SO
|
|
la̰ʔškamaniːníːn kaːmaškíːɬ ḭščiká̰n gobierno
|
PO V SO S
|
|
gobierno la̰ʔškamaniːníːn
kaːmaškíːɬ ḭščiká̰n
|
S PO V SO,
etc.
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Although
utterances in which all arguments are realized as NPs are relatively uncommon,
sentences with all possible orders can be found in the corpus and are accepted
during elicitation.
Copular clauses show flexible ordering of subject and predicate
phrase, but the copula, when present, is preceded immediately by its complement
in all but a few examples:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(10)
|
šantíɬ šwanḭ́ː tsa̰má puskáːt
|
|
šantíɬ
|
ḭš–wan–nḭː
|
tsa̰má
|
puskáːt
|
|
shaman
|
past–be–pf
|
that
|
woman
|
|
‘That woman
was a shaman.’
|
|
|
|
tsa̰má puskáːt šantíɬ šwanḭ́ː
|
|
*tsa̰má puskáːt šwanḭ́ː šantíɬ
|
|
*šantíɬ tsa̰má puskáːt šwanḭ́ː
|
|
?šwanḭ́ː šantíɬ tsa̰má puskáːt
|
The
final order shown here occurs occasionally, most often in the context of
elicitation-by-translation of Spanish sentences, but it is usually rejected or
corrected by speakers when offered. It seems likely to be an effect of calquing
from Spanish (cf. era
bruja esa mujer).
Like predicate complements, most types of adverbial are also
required to precede the verb:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(11)
|
liːškamaniːntṵnká̰
ḭšwíːɬ naḭščík tsa̰má puskáːt
|
|
liː–škamaníːn=tṵnká̰
|
ḭš–wiːɬ
|
nak=ḭš–čík
|
tsa̰má
|
puskáːt
|
|
gnc–pauper=very
|
past–sit
|
loc=3poss–house
|
that
|
woman
|
|
‘The woman
lived in great poverty in her house.’
|
|
|
|
liːškamaniːntṵnká̰ naḭščík ḭšwíːɬ
tsa̰má puskáːt
|
|
liːškamaniːntṵnká̰
ḭšwíːɬ tsa̰má puskáːt naḭščík
|
|
liːškamaniːntṵnká̰ tsa̰má puskáːt ḭšwíːɬ
naḭščík
|
|
*ḭšwíːɬ
liːškamaniːntṵnká̰ naḭščík tsa̰má puskáːt
|
Ideophones
as well as dynamic, configurational, descriptive, and manner adverbs
obligatorily precede their verbal heads, while temporal and locative adverbials
like naḭščík ‘in her house’ in (11) may be either pre-verbal or post-verbal
(Beck 2008).
Constituent ordering is also relatively more fixed in information
questions (a.k.a. wh-questions), which require that the interrogative
pronoun be the first element in the clause:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(12)
|
tiː namín?
|
|
tiː
|
na–min
|
|
who
|
fut–come
|
|
‘Who is
coming?’
|
(13)
|
tuː liːmá̰ʔnḭː?
|
|
tuː
|
liː–má̰ʔnḭː
|
|
what
|
inst–kill:2sg.sub:pfv
|
|
‘What did
you kill it with?’
|
Questions
can be formed on any clausal constituent. In addition to tiː
‘who?’ and tuː ‘what?’, Upper Necaxa has the
interrogatives xa̰ː ‘where?’ and xá̰ːkšnḭ ‘when?’,
the former but not the later also being homophonous with the corresponding
relativizer.
Relative clauses
in Upper Necaxa Totonac are first described in Beck (2004), where they are
characterized as being externally-headed or headless, with a gapped argument
inside the embedded clause. Relatives are introduced by what is characterized
as a relativizer, either tuː or tiː,
depending on the animacy of the head of the construction. Example (14) illustrates a
relative clause with an inanimate nominal head:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(14)
|
yúxa
tsa̰má škaːn [tuː wanḭkán čá̰ːwa̰]
|
|
yux–a
|
tsa̰má
|
škaːn
|
[tuː
|
wan–nḭ–kan
|
ØSO
|
čá̰ːwa̰]
|
|
go.down–impf
|
that
|
water
|
nrel
|
say–ben–idf
|
__
|
sooty.water
|
|
‘The water
that they call “čá̰ːwa̰” comes down.’
|
The
head of the relative clause is škaːn ‘water’ and corresponds to the
gapped object of the intransitive verb wanḭ́ ‘X calls Y
Z’. The clause follows its head and is introduced by the non-human relativizer,
tuː. The relativizer appears on the left edge of the
clause and in most cases immediately follows the modified noun, although there
are a few examples from texts in which the relative clause is separated from
its head, as in (15):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(15)
|
ḭštaa̰kɬmaːštuní
ḭštumiːnká̰n ḭšpuskaːtká̰n [tuː tsa̰x šmaːn nataliːwá púɬkḭ]
|
|
ḭš–ta–a̰kɬmaːštú–ní
|
ḭš–tumíːn–ka̰n
|
ḭš–puskáːt–ka̰n
|
[tuː
|
tsa̰x
|
|
past–3pl.sub–set.aside–ben
|
3poss–money–pl.po
|
3poss–wife–pl.po
|
nrel
|
only
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
šmaːn
|
na–ta–liː–wa
|
púɬkḭ
|
ØSO]
|
|
only
|
fut–3pl.sub–inst–eat
|
pulque
|
__
|
|
‘They hid
some of their money from their wives which they would use to drink pulque.’
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
The
relative clause in (15), tu: tsa̰x šmaːn nataliːwá púɬkḭ
‘which they would use to drink pulque’, modifies the noun ḭštumiːnká̰n
‘their money’, the secondary object of the embedded verb, but is separated from
it by the NP ḭšpuskaːtká̰n ‘their wives’.
Example (16) shows a relative clause introduced by the human relativizer, tiː:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
|
(16)
|
tačinʔó̰ːɬ
na̰ščiká̰n tsa̰má kɾistiánṵ [tiː xaː kaːleːní ḭščiká̰n]
|
|
|
ta–čin–ʔo̰ː–ɬ
|
nak=ḭš–čik–ka̰n
|
tsa̰má
|
kɾistiánṵ
|
|
3pl.sub–arrive–tot–pfv
|
loc=3poss–house–pl.po
|
that
|
person
|
|
|
|
|
[tiː
|
xaː
|
kaː–leːn–nḭ
|
ØSO
|
ḭš–čik–ka̰n]
|
|
|
hrel
|
neg
|
pl.obj–take.away–ben
|
__
|
3poss–house–pl.po
|
|
|
‘They all
came to the houses of the people from whom (the flood) hadn’t taken their
homes.’
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
In
this example, the head of the relative clause, kɾistiánṵ
‘person’, corresponds to an object of the embedded verb leːnḭ́ ‘X
takes Y away from Z’. The form of the relativizer indicates that the head of
the clause is human, but gives no indication of its number.
Relatives can also be formed from copular clauses, as in (17):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(17)
|
ḭkla̰ʔapása puskáːt [tiː šantíɬ šwanḭ́ː]
|
|
ḭk–la̰ʔapás–a
|
puskáːt
|
[tiː
|
šantíɬ
|
ḭš–wan–nḭː
|
ØSUB]
|
|
1sg.sub–know–impf
|
woman
|
hrel
|
shaman
|
past–be–pf
|
__
|
|
‘I know the
woman who was a shaman.’
|
As
in the previous examples, the relative clause immediately follows the noun it
modifies and is introduced by a relativizer, in this case tiː,
which encodes the animacy of the head.
Headless relative clauses are illustrated in (18) and (19):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(18)
|
wiːɬ
[tiː kiliːa̰ʔšpaːwaká̰ɬ]
|
|
wiːɬ
|
[tiː
|
kin–liː–a̰ʔšpaː–waká̰ɬ
|
ØSUB]
|
|
sit
|
hrel
|
1obj–inst–back.of.head–be.high
|
__
|
|
‘There is
someone resting their head on me.’
|
(19)
|
aː
wiːɬ [tuː pṵtsapá̰ː]
|
|
aː
|
wiːɬ
|
[tuː
|
pṵtsá–pa̰ː
|
ØPO]
|
|
there
|
sit
|
nrel
|
look.for–prog:2sg.sub
|
__
|
|
‘There is
what you are looking for.’
|
In
both of these sentences, the matrix verb is wiːɬ,
which literally means ‘be sitting’ but is also used as a general existential
locative (≈ Eng. ‘be there’). The headless relatives in both examples take the
role of matrix subject. The relative clause in (18) is a subject-centred clause, introduced by tiː,
with an animate referent, while that in (19) is an object-centred clause, introduced by tuː,
with an inanimate referent.
Headless relatives formed on copular clauses are also attested, both
with and without an overt copula:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(20)
|
ḭkla̰ʔapása [tiː šantíːɬ šwanḭ́ː]
|
|
ḭk–la̰ʔapás–a
|
[tiː
|
šantíːɬ
|
ḭš–wan–nḭ́ː
|
ØSUB]
|
|
1sg.sub–recognize–impf
|
hrel
|
shaman
|
past–be–pf
|
__
|
|
‘I know the
one who was a shaman.’
|
(21)
|
ḭkʔawaxní tuː šamásnḭ
|
|
ḭk–ʔawaxní
|
[tuː
|
ša–mas–nḭ
|
ØSUB]
|
|
1sg.sub–disgusted
|
nrel
|
dtv–rot–nmlzr
|
__
|
|
‘I am
disgusted by things that are rotten.’
|
Such
clauses are necessarily subject-centred, as relative-clauses centred on a
predicate-complement seem impossible, or at least difficult to conceive of.
Research subsequent to 2004 has shown that, in addition to
externally-headed and headless relatives, Upper Necaxa also has
internally-headed relative clauses like those in (22):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(22)
|
ɬúːwa̰
[tiː tas’o̰ʔanán tsṵma̰xáːn]
|
|
ɬúːwa̰
|
[tiː
|
ta–s’o̰ʔá–nan
|
tsṵma̰xáːt–n]
|
|
many
|
hrel
|
3pl.sub–hug–sapsv
|
girl–pl
|
|
‘There are a
lot of girls who hug.’
|
In (22), the head of the
relative clause, tsṵma̰xáːn ‘girls’, corresponds to
the plural subject of the antipassivized verb, s’o̰ʔanán
‘X gives hugs’, and occurs inside what is otherwise identical to a headless
relative construction such as that in (18). That these constructions are indeed
internally-headed, rather than right-headed, can be seen in (23):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(23)
|
po̰ʔɬ
kintama̰ʔalakawán [tiː tsax šmaːn taliːtatsḛ́ʔa tsa̰má ʔawa̰čá̰n ḭstsḭːká̰n]
|
|
po̰ʔɬ
|
kin–ta–ma̰ʔa–laka–wan
|
[tiː
|
tsax
|
šmaːn
|
|
fed.up
|
1obj–3pl.sub–stm–face–say
|
hrel
|
just
|
only
|
|
|
|
ta–liː–ta–tsḛʔ–a
|
tsa̰má
|
ʔawa̰čá̰–n
|
ḭš–tsḭː–ka̰n]
|
|
3pl.sub–inst–dcs–hide–impf
|
that
|
boy–pl
|
3poss–mother–pl.po
|
|
‘Those boys that
hide behind their mother(’s skirts) really bother me.’
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Here
the head of the construction is ʔawa̰čá̰n ‘boys’. It functions as the
subject of the embedded verb, li:tatsḛ́ʔ- ‘X hides behind Y’, which
is inflected for a third-person plural subject, and appears followed by the
verb’s object, ḭstsḭːká̰n ‘their mother(s)’. Such
constructions, while not abundant, occur naturally in spontaneous speech and
are accepted readily in elicitation. Thus, it seems that Upper Necaxa allows
for three types of relative clause—externally-headed, headless, and
internally-headed.
Other than the presence of the relativizer, Upper Necaxa relative
clauses seem virtually identical to matrix clauses and show the same
flexibility with respect to the ordering of arguments—although there is a
dispreference for arguments of the embedded clause in pre-verbal position. Such
constructions are difficult to elicit, but examples such as (24) are found in
texts:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(24)
|
[tiː šteːkṵtṵnká̰
škaːn šwanḭkán]
|
|
[tiː
|
ḭš–téːkṵ=tṵnká̰
|
škaːn
|
ḭš–wan–nḭ–kan
|
ØSO]
|
|
|
hrel
|
3poss–owner=very
|
water
|
past–say–ben–idf
|
__
|
|
|
‘the one
that they call the spirit of the water himself’
|
In
this example, the primary object, ḭštéːkṵ škaːn ‘the
spirit of the water’, precedes rather than follows the verb. Fronting of
arguments in general seems to be associated with focalization (Mel’čuk 2001),
and in the examples where an element inside a relative clause is fronted there
is a clear emphatic or focal attention on that element. In (24), this is reflected
by the presence of the intensifying clitic =tṵnká̰
and the Spanish gloss given by the consultant, el mero dueno del agua ‘the very/the one and only spirit of the water’.
Similarly, adverbials also maintain the pre-verbal position found in
matrix clauses:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
|
(25)
|
ča̰ːtín
puskáːt [tiː liːškamaníːn ḭšwíːɬ naḭščík]
|
|
|
ča̰ː–tin
|
puskáːt
|
[tiː
|
liː–škamaníːn
|
ḭš–wiːɬ
|
Øsub
|
nak=ḭš–čik]
|
|
clf–one
|
woman
|
hrel
|
inst–pauper
|
past–sit
|
__
|
loc=3poss–house
|
|
‘a woman who
lived in poverty in her house’
|
|
|
|
|
|
ča̰ːtín puskáːt [tiː liːškamaniːntṵnká̰
naḭščík ḭšwíːɬ]
|
|
|
*ča̰ːtín
puskáːt [tiː ḭšwíːɬ liːškamaniːntṵnká̰ naḭščík]
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
As
shown in (25), the manner adverb obligatorily precedes the verb, while the
locative is permitted in either pre-verbal or post-verbal position. These rules
of constituent order apply both when the clause is headless and when it is
internally, rather than externally, headed.
In terms of accessibility to relativization, Upper Necaxa allows for
the relativization of elements of all applicable ranks on the Accessibility
Hierarchy (Keenan and Comrie 1977). Examples of relatives centred on subjects,
primary objects, secondary objects and possessors can be found in
texts. The
sentence in (26) shows a subject-centred relative clause:
|
Upper
Necaxa Totonac
|
(26)
|
ḭkɬoːpalá
ḭščoʍká̰n lakstín [tiː taá̰n nakskwéla]
|
|
ḭk–ɬawá–palá
|
ḭš–čoʍ–ka̰n
|
lakstín
|
[tiː
|
ta–a̰n
|
ØSUB
|
|
1sg.sub–make–rpt
|
3poss–tortilla–pl.po
|
children
|
hrel
|
3pl.sub–go
|
__
|
|
nak=skwela]
|
|
loc=school
|
|
‘I
make food again for the children that go to school.’
|
Here,
the head of the relative clause lakstín ‘children’ is coreferential
with the subject of the embedded verb, taá̰n ‘they go’. A
headless subject-centred relative clause is shown in (27):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(27)
|
ḭkta̰ʔaːšnimáːɬ
wačḭ́ wiːɬ [tuː nakilaní]
|
|
ḭk–ta–ʔaːšní–maːɬ
|
wačḭ́
|
wiːɬ
|
[tuː
|
na–kin–laní
|
ØSUB]
|
|
1sg.sub–dcs–feel.forboding–prog
|
apparently
|
sit
|
nrel
|
fut–1obj–happen.to
|
__
|
|
‘I feel like
there is something that is going to happen to me.’
|
The
headless relative here is based on the verb laní
‘X happens affecting Y’, which is formed by adding the benefactive applicative -nḭ́
to the light verb la ‘X happens’. The gapped argument
corresponds to the subject of the verb, the event that happens and affects Y.
Internally-headed subject-centred relative clauses are also attested as in (28):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(28)
|
kalá̰ʔtsḭ,
[tiː natawilá ḭs’á̰ta̰], nakšá̰ː namaːša̰ːa̰niːkán
|
|
ka–lá̰ʔtsḭ
|
[tiː
|
na–tawilá
|
ḭš–s’á̰ta̰]
|
nak=šá̰ː
|
|
opt–see:2sg.sub:pfv
|
hrel
|
fut–be.born
|
3poss–child
|
loc=sweatlodge
|
|
na–maː–ša̰ː–a̰n–niː–kan
|
|
fut–caus–sweatlodge–go–caus–idf
|
|
‘Look, a child that
will be born, they will bathe it in the sweatlodge.’
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Relatives
formed on copular clauses can also be internally-headed:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(29)
|
ḭkla̰ʔapása [tiː
šantíːɬ šwanḭ́ː puskáːt]
|
|
ḭk–la̰ʔapás–a
|
[tiː
|
šantíːɬ
|
ḭš–wan–nḭː
|
puskáːt]
|
|
|
1sg.sub–recognize–impf
|
hrel
|
shaman
|
past–be–pf
|
woman
|
|
|
‘I know a woman who was a shaman.’
|
Not
unexpectedly, then, it appears that all subjects are accessible to
relativization.
In terms of object relations, both primary and secondary objects are
accessible. In (30), we see a relative clause centred on the sole (primary) object of
the transitive verb la̰ʔatíː ‘X likes Y’:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(30)
|
wḭš
kalaksáktḭ [tiː tsex la̰ʔatíːya̰]
|
|
wḭš
|
ka–laksák–tḭ
|
[tiː
|
tsex
|
la̰ʔatíː–ya̰
|
ØPO]
|
|
you
|
opt–choose–2sg.sub:pfv
|
hrel
|
well
|
like–impf:2sg.sub
|
__
|
|
‘Pick the
one (girl) that you like best!’
|
(31) also shows a
headless primary-object centred relative clause:
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(31)
|
tḭyá̰ʔ
laklaɬtsá̰, xaːtsá̰ la [tuː ča̰nkán]
|
|
tḭyá̰ʔ
|
laklá–ɬ=tsá̰
|
xaː=tsá̰
|
la
|
[tuː
|
ča̰n–kan
|
ØPO]
|
|
land
|
ruined–pfv=now
|
neg=now
|
do
|
nrel
|
plant–idf
|
__
|
|
‘The earth
is ruined, what you plant doesn’t grow.’
|
The
reference of the relative clause in (31) is to the object of the verb ča̰n
‘X plants Y’. In this example, the verb ča̰n
is inflected for the indefinite voice, which suppresses the expression of the
subject but does not promote a first- or third-person object to subject
position (Beck 2004, 2016). Verbs in this voice have either an indefinite
subject (≈ Eng. indefinite they or you) or a reflexive reading.
An internally-headed primary-object centred relative clause is
shown in (32):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(32)
|
xaː
kɬoːkṵtún [tuː kɬoːmáːɬ kintaskuxút]
|
|
xaː
|
ḭk–ɬawá–kṵtún
|
[tuː
|
ḭk–ɬawá–maːɬ
|
kin–taskuxút]
|
|
|
neg
|
1sg.sub–make–dsd
|
nrel
|
1sg.sub–make–prog
|
1poss–job
|
|
|
‘I don’t
want to do my job that I’m doing.’
|
The
head of the relative clause is the primary object of ɬawa
‘X does Y’, kintaskuxút ‘my job’, and it appears
in this sentence inside the embedded clause.
An externally-headed secondary-object centred relative clause is
shown in (33):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(33)
|
yaːwaːnḭkán
a̰ʔtín [tuː liːlakaɬtaŋteːkán]
|
|
yaːwáː–nḭ–kan
|
a̰ʔ–tin
|
[tuː
|
liː–laka–ɬtaŋ–tayá–kan
|
ØSO]
|
|
stand–ben–idf
|
clf–one
|
nrel
|
inst–face–pull.taut–take–idf
|
__
|
|
‘They stood
up against it something that they could use to pull it tight.’
|
In (33), the head of the
relative clause is the applied, secondary object of the verb liːlakaɬtaŋtayá
‘X pulls Y taut with Z’, formed from the verb lakaɬtaŋtayá
‘X pulls Y taut’ with the instrumental applicative prefix liː-.
Note that in this example the head of the relative clause is a numeral
classifier construction used anaphorically to mean ‘something’, although unlike
the English something in the gloss, the expression is not necessarily
indefinite (that is, in the right context the relative might have been translated
as ‘the thing that they could use to pull it tight’).
A headless secondary-object centred relative clause is shown in (34):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(34)
|
ḭšyúxa
naka̰ʔapúːn [tuː šwanḭkán pḭčáːwa̰]
|
|
ḭš–yux–a
|
nak=a̰ʔapúːn
|
[tuː
|
ḭš–wan–nḭ́–kan
|
pḭčáːwa̰
|
ØSO]
|
|
past–go.down–impf
|
loc=sky
|
nrel
|
past–say–ben–idf
|
eagle
|
__
|
|
‘The one
they called the Pichawa came down from the sky.’
|
The
referent of the clause here is the animal being named, which corresponds to the
applied object of the verb waní ‘X says Y to Z’, the translation
equivalent of English call/name, which is formed from the verb wan ‘X says Y’ by adding the benefactive applicative suffix -nḭ.
The same verb can be seen in an internally-headed secondary-object centred
relative clause in (35):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(35)
|
čuːntsáː
čḭ wa̰má liːtawilanḭ́ː [tuː wanḭkán šliːčḭkiːtawíːɬ Patla]
|
|
čuːntsáː
|
čḭ
|
wa̰má
|
liː–tawilá–nḭː
|
[tuː
|
wan–nḭ–kan
|
|
thus
|
how
|
this
|
inst–sit–pf
|
nrel
|
say–ben–idf
|
|
ḭš–liːčḭkiːtawíːɬ
|
Patla]
|
|
3poss–town
|
Patla
|
|
‘That is the way
their town that they named Patla was founded.’
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
In (35) the head of the
relative is the object being named, ḭšliːčḭkiːtawíːɬ ‘their
town’, which is realized inside the embedded clause, to the left of the primary
object, the name Patla.
The only type of construction that is clearly a relative clause
centred on an adjunct is the locative-centred relative. Locative-centred
relatives are introduced by xa̰ː ‘where’, as in (36):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(36)
|
kit ḭkla̰ʔtawaká̰ɬ na̰šʔéːn čik [xa̰ːš
waka̰čá kimpelota]
|
|
kit
|
ḭk–la̰ʔ–ta–waká̰–ɬ
|
nak–ḭš–ʔeːn
|
čik
|
[xa̰ː
|
ḭš–waká̰–čá
|
|
I
|
1sg.sub–altv–dcs–be.high
|
loc=3poss–back
|
house
|
where
|
past–be.high–dist
|
|
kin–pelota
|
ØLOC]
|
|
1poss–ball
|
__
|
|
‘I’m going to get up there on the roof of my house where my ball
went.’
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Perhaps
unsurprisingly, locative-centred relatives are more frequently headless, as in (37):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(37)
|
na̰ká̰n
maːla̰ʔapasníː xa̰ː naɬa̰ːwán
|
|
na–ḭk–a̰n
|
maː–la̰ʔapás–niː
|
[xa̰ː
|
na–ɬa̰ːwán
|
ØLOC]
|
|
|
fut–1sg.sub–go
|
caus–recognize–caus
|
where
|
fut–walk
|
__
|
|
|
‘I’m going
to go show him where he’s going to walk.’
|
While
locative relatives seem to share some of the properties of relative clauses
introduced by tiː and tuː,
little more will be said about them in the remainder of this paper. Likewise,
there are temporal constructions introduced by a̰kšní
‘when’ that look very similar to relative clauses, but are not clearly attested
modifying nouns. These will also be left aside in this discussion.
Moving further down the Accessibility Hierarchy, a look through the
corpus finds possessor-centred relative clauses, like those in (38) and (39):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(38)
|
kaːšɬawáka̰ čik [tuː la̰ʔapá̰ʔɬa ḭšventana]
|
|
kaːšɬawá–ka̰
|
čik
|
[tuː
|
la̰ʔa–pa̰ʔɬ–a
|
ḭš–ventana
|
ØPOSS]
|
|
repair–idf:pfv
|
house
|
nrel
|
face–break–impf
|
3poss=window
|
__
|
|
‘They
repaired the house whose windows s/he broke.’
|
(39)
|
kaːma̰ʔtaːyáka̰
ma̰ʔa̰ːpḭtsḭ́n kɾistiánṵ [tiː ḭštanuːnḭ́ː puːɬúːn naḭščík]
|
|
kaː–ma̰ʔtaːyá–ka̰
|
ma̰ʔa̰ːpḭ́tsḭ–n
|
kɾistiánṵ
|
[tiː
|
ḭš–tanúː–nḭː
|
puːɬúːn
|
|
pl.obj–help–idf:pfv
|
some–pl
|
person
|
hrel
|
past–enter–pf
|
mud
|
|
|
|
nak=ḭš–čík
|
ØPOSS]
|
|
loc=3poss–house
|
__
|
|
‘They helped
some of the people whose houses the mud had gotten into.’
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Headless and internally-headed versions of relatives of either the possessor- or comparative-centred types have not been found or elicited, though it seems entirely possible this is simply a gap in the data rather than a specific grammatical restriction, like that
in (40):
|
Upper Necaxa Totonac
|
(40)
|
ḭkpṵtsá
ča̰ːtín tsṵma̰xáːt [tiː aːčuláː tseːwanḭ́ čḭ wḭš]
|
|
ḭk–pṵtsá
|
ča̰ː–tin
|
tsṵma̰xáːt
|
[tiː
|
aːčuláː
|
tseːwanḭ́
|
ØSUB
|
čḭ
|
wḭš]
|
|
|
1sg.sub–look.for
|
clf–one
|
girl
|
hrel
|
more
|
pretty
|
__
|
like
|
you
|
|
|
‘I’m looking
for a girl who is prettier than you.’
|
As we’ve seen in
the preceding section, Upper Necaxa takes a rather free-wheeling approach to
relativization, allowing externally-headed, headless, and internally-headed
constructions, and permitting relativization along nearly the full length of the
Accessibility Hierarchy. Constituent order in relative clauses continues to be
flexible, though there seem to be discourse conditions on “fronting” NPs to a
position between the verb and the relativizer. The relativizers themselves make
a human/non-human animacy distinction and, in this respect (showing some sort
of agreement with the head of the relative construction), resemble pronouns.
Taken together, this is an unusual typological profile, particularly with
respect to the presence of internally-headed relative clauses. According to
Dryer (2013), internally-headed relative clauses are rare, found in only 63
languages in his 824-language sample (7.6%) and occurring as a non-dominant
(less frequent) type in only 10 (1%). The fact that internally-headed relatives
in Upper Necaxa are not in any sense nominalized contradicts a universalist
claim made in de Vries (2005: 18) that such structures are always nominalized,
and are only found in languages that have a similar type nominalized
non-relative clauses (which Upper Necaxa lacks). Likewise, de Vries (2005: 19)
claims that internally-headed relatives should only be found in languages with
RelN and NDet order, neither of which is true of Upper Necaxa, although a loose
correlation of RelN order with the presence of internally-headed relatives
clauses appears to be borne out by the data in Dryer (2013). In the
(surprising) absence of large-scale, quantitative typological studies of the
Accessibility Hierarchy, it is not possible to determine how unusual access to
such a wide range of elements on the Hierarchy is, though presumably it is
relatively infrequent given the number of other possible language types
foreseen by the Hierarchy. Given the interesting profile of Upper Necaxa
relative clauses, it seems worthwhile at this point to turn to other languages
in the family, with an eye towards seeing what, if any, of these features are
shared by other languages in the group, and if the familial pattern sheds any
light on the nature of the Upper Necaxa relativizers.
The internal
structure of the Totonacan family is still not well understood, though, as
shown in Figure 2, it is generally agreed that Totonacan languages can be divided at
the highest level into two branches, Tepehua and Totonac. Tepehua is considered
to consist of three languages—Tlachichilco, Pisaflores, and Huehuetla, while
Totonac is more highly ramified and contains an as-yet-unknown number of
languages. The most basal division in the Totonac branch of the family is
between the geographical outlier Misantla Totonac and the remaining Central Totonac
languages. Central Totonac has traditionally been held to consist of three
sub-groupings—Northern, Sierra (a.k.a. Highland), and Lowland (Papantla).
Beyond this, the relations become murkier, and there have been various
proposals for grouping together Northern and Sierra against Lowland (García
Rojas 1978), Lowland and Northern against Sierra (MacKay and Trechsel 2014,
2015), and Northern against Lowland-Sierra (Ichon 1969; Davletshin 2008; Brown
et al. 2011). Presently, the weight of the evidence, particularly the lexical
evidence, seems to favour the last of these. There are, in addition, further
uncertainties, and particularly problematic are the affiliations of Cerro
Xinolatépetl and Filomeno Mata. While Cerro Xinolatépetl is not spoken in an
area contiguous with Lowland-Sierra languages (see Figure 1 above),
lexical evidence suggests its affinity is with these rather than with the
adjacent Northern group. Filomeno Mata is grouped by MacKay and Trechsel (2014)
in the Northern branch, based on shared morphological characteristics, and it
does seem to be the case that this language also shares a few lexical forms
with the Northern languages; however, the bulk of the lexical isoglosses, as
well as statistical measures of lexical similarity, seem to point to a closer
affiliation with Lowland-Sierra.
TEPEHUA
|
|
Tlachichilco
|
|
|
Pisaflores
|
|
|
Huehuetla
|
|
TOTONAC
|
|
Misantla
|
|
CENTRAL TOTONAC
|
|
NORTHERN TOTONAC
|
|
|
Apapantilla
|
|
|
Zihuateutla
|
|
|
Upper Necaxa
|
|
|
Coahuitlán
|
|
SOUTH CENTRAL–LOWLAND
|
|
|
Cerro Xinolatépetl
|
|
|
|
|
Filomeno Mata
|
|
|
|
|
|
LOWLAND-SIERRA
|
|
|
|
|
LOWLAND
|
|
|
|
|
|
Cerro del Carbón
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Escolín
|
|
|
|
|
|
SIERRA
|
|
|
|
|
|
Coyutla
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Coatepec
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Zapotitlán
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Huehuetla
Totonac
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Olintla
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Ozelonacaxtla
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Figure
2. Totonacan languages
In terms of available descriptions of relativization strategies in
Totonacan languages, the pickings are rather slim. For Tepehua, Smythe-Kung
(2007) offers a sketch of relativization in Huehuetla, and some mention of
relative clauses in Tlachichilco is made at various points in Watters (1988).
In Northern Totonac, relative clauses are mentioned in passing in the pedagogical
grammar of Apapantilla prepared by Reid (1991) and there are numerous
unanalyzed examples in a lexical database for the language prepared by Reid et
al. (n.d.). Relative clauses in Sierra languages are dealt with indirectly for
Huehuetla Totonac in Troiani (2004) and for Coatepec in McQuown (1990). E.
Aschmann (1984) presents a much more thorough and detailed description of all
types of relatives in Zapotitlán Totonac, and additional examples from this
language (again, unanalyzed) can be found in the lexical database prepared by
H. Aschmann (n.d.a). Likewise, a large number of unanalyzed sentences that
contain relative clauses can be found in the examples in H. Aschmann’s (n.d.b)
lexical database for the Sierra Totonac language Coyutla. Unanalyzed
translations of Spanish sentences containing relative clauses can be found for
Misantla Totonac in MacKay and Trechsel (2005), and one or two examples of
relatives can be found in analyzed texts in MacKay (1999) and MacKay and
Trechsel (2012b). Beyond this, information on a few other languages can be
gleaned from the interlinearized texts in Levy and Beck (2012) which contain
examples of relative clauses from the Totonac languages Cerro Xinolatépetl,
Filomeno Mata, Olintla, Ozelonacaxtla, and Cerro del Carbón, and for all three
Tepehua languages. In the sections that follow, I will summarize what can be
extracted from this fragmentary data, beginning with Tepehua in section 3.2 and then moving on
to the Totonac group in section 3.3.
The most
detailed description of relative clauses in Tepehua languages is found in
Smythe-Kung’s (2007) doctoral dissertation on Huehuetla Tepehua. Smythe-Kung
gives examples of both externally-headed post-nominal (41) and headless (42) relative
constructions:
|
Huehuetla Tepehua
|
(41)
|
štaʔamaqpanan
huː papaːnin [huː kaː waː lakak’iwin štat’ahun]
|
|
š–ta–ʔamaqpanan
|
huː
|
papaʔ–nin
|
[huː
|
kaː
|
waː
|
laka–k’iwin
|
|
past–3pl.sub–wash.clothes
|
art
|
man–pl
|
rel
|
blv
|
foc
|
prep–woods
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
š–ta–t’ahun
|
ØSUB]
|
|
past–3pl.sub–live
|
__
|
|
‘The men that were
living in the woods would wash their clothes.’
|
|
(Smythe-Kung 2007:
590)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
[huː šʔulaːta tam p’aqlati tuːmiːn]
|
(42)
|
[huː
|
š–ʔulaː–ta
|
ØSUB
|
tam
|
p’aqlati
|
tuːmiːn]
|
|
rel
|
past–put–pf
|
__
|
one
|
chest
|
money
|
|
‘the one who had a
chest (full) of money’
|
|
(Smythe-Kung 2007:
597)
|
In
both cases, these are subject-centred relative clauses introduced by a
relativizer, huː, which is homophonous with the
article that is found introducing noun phrases such as the head of the relative
clause in (41), huː papaːnin ‘the men’. The relativizer,
like the article, is invariant and shows no agreement for number or animacy.
Although Smythe-Kung makes no explicit reference to constituent order within
the clause, none of her examples have fronted arguments and nothing precedes
verbs except adverbial elements such as particles and the locative phrase seen
in (41).
The issue of noun-phrase accessibility in Huehuetla is complicated
by the fact that the terminology used in the description of this language does
not map directly onto the categories traditionally used in the discussion of
the Acessiblity Hierarchy. According to Smythe Kung (2007: 592),
externally-headed relative clauses can be formed on subjects, direct objects,
indirect objects, oblique objects, and locative adjuncts. For Smythe Kung,
direct objects are the single objects of transitive verbs, and indirect objects
are the recipients in ditransitive verbs such as that in (43):
|
Huehuetla Tepehua
|
(43)
|
puːs
kaː yuːč [huː ʔištaqnitač]
|
|
puːs
|
kaː
|
yuːč
|
[huː
|
ʔiš–štaq–ni–ta=č
|
ØINDIRECT.OBJ
]
|
|
well
|
blv
|
3sg.pro
|
rel
|
past–give–dat–pf=ald
|
__
|
|
‘Well, I think that
it was he to whom she had given it.’
|
|
(Smythe Kung 2007:
596)
|
The
embedded verb in (43) is štaqni ‘X give Y to Z’ which contains
a fossilized instance of the dative applicative, -ni.
Other applicatives such as t’aː- ‘comitative’ add what Smythe
Kung calls “oblique” objects, as in (44):
|
Huehuetla Tepehua
|
(44)
|
tiːsčawayč
[huː t’aːʔot’i]
|
|
tiːsčawayč
|
[huː
|
t’aː–qot–t’i
|
ØOBLIQUE.OBJ
]
|
|
who
|
rel
|
cmt–drink–2sg.sub:pfv
|
__
|
|
‘With whom was it
that you drank?’
|
|
(Smythe Kung 2007:
596)
|
However,
objects like these are oblique only in the semantic sense that they are not
part of the basic valency of the verb; syntactically, it is not clear that they
are oblique objects in the usual meaning of the term and, based on descriptions
of applied objects in Tlachichilco (Watters 1989), they would probably not be
considered “oblique” by Keenan and Comrie (1977), although they would still
rank below direct objects and above locative adjuncts.
As in Upper Necaxa, locative relatives in Huehuetla Totonac make use
of a separate element meaning ‘where’ to introduce the subordinate clause:
|
Huehuetla Tepehua
|
(45)
|
waː
ʔalin taɬpa [huntaː ktapaːsayaw]
|
|
waː
|
ʔalin
|
taɬpa
|
[huntaː
|
ktapaːsayaw
|
ØLOC ]
|
|
foc
|
there.is
|
hill
|
where
|
1sub–pass–impf–1pl.sub:pfv
|
__
|
|
‘There is a hill
where we pass …’
|
|
(Smythe Kung 2007:
598)
|
In
Huehuetla, however, huntaː ‘where’, is not homophonous
with the interrogative word for questioning locations, ta̰nč
‘where?’ (Smythe Kung 2007: 567), and in this it differs from Upper Necaxa
Totonac.
There is less information available about headless relatives in
Huehuetla. Although Smythe Kung (2007: 592) writes that these are confined to
subject-centred constructions, there is some evidence that other types of
headless relatives are possible, as shown by the following example from the
text in Smythe Kung (2012):
|
Huehuetla Tepehua
|
(46)
|
huː ʔanuːč [huː ʔulaːta huː purowiː huː
lapanak]
|
|
huː
|
ʔanuʔ=č
|
huː
|
ʔulaː–ta
|
huː
|
purowiː
|
huː
|
lapanak
|
ØOBJ
|
|
art
|
that=now
|
rel
|
put–pf
|
art
|
pauper
|
art
|
person
|
—
|
|
‘what the pauper,
the person had put there’
|
|
(Smythe Kung 2012:
71, line 26)
|
Here,
the referent of the headless relative clause corresponds to the object of the
verb ʔulaː ‘X places Y’. It may be that the constraint
against headless relatives formed on non-subjects noted by Smythe Kung is more
of a dispreference than an absolute prohibition, and additional examples may
surface in future investigations.
Relative clauses in Tlachichilco Tepehua have not been described in
detail, although a few examples and some structural observations about them can
be found in Watters (1988: 120, 461–2, 467–72). According to Watters, both
externally-headed (47) and headless (48) relative clauses can be formed from any “direct argument” of the
verb:
|
Tlachichilco Tepehua
|
(47)
|
ni
ka:ɾoh [yuː kpuːmiɬ] yuːča waː ʔaɬča
|
|
ni
|
ka:ɾoh
|
[yuː
|
k–puː–min–ɬ
|
ØOBJ ]
|
yuːča
|
waː
|
ʔan–ɬ=ča
|
|
art
|
car
|
rel
|
1sub–via–come–pfv
|
__
|
3pro
|
foc
|
go–pfv=now
|
|
‘The car I came in,
it’s gone already.’
|
(48)
|
[yuː kint’aːmiɬ]
waː kilaqah
|
|
[yuː
|
kin–t’aː–min–ɬ
|
ØOBJ ]
|
waː
|
kin–laqah
|
|
rel
|
1obj–cmt–come–pfv
|
__
|
foc
|
1poss–kinsman
|
|
‘The one I came
with is my relative(male).’
|
|
(Watters 1988:
120)
|
In
both of these examples, the target of relativization is an applied object added
to the valency of the verb by an applicative—puː-
‘means, path’ in (47) and t’aː- ‘comitative’ in (48). Watters (1988)
also presents examples of subject- (p. 472) and direct-object centred (p. 462)
relative clauses, but does not mention the possibility of forming relative
clauses on locative expressions.
As in Huehuetla, in Tlachichilco relative clauses are introduced by
an element, yuː, that is homophonous with a
determiner also used to introduce noun phrases—although, unlike Huehuetla,
Tlachichilco has other determiners as well, and the one used with relative
clauses is textually less-frequent (Watters 1988: 466). This also seems to be
true of Pisaflores Tepehua, judging by the text in MacKay and Trechsel (2012a),
where the cognate element, yuu, is glossed as ‘that’ or ‘the one
that’ when introducing relative clauses, both externally-headed (49) and headless (50):
|
Pisaflores Tepehua
|
(49)
|
máaʔá̰ɬča
ʔá̰n lapánaak [yúu máalaʔa̰čáakaɬ]
|
|
maa–an–ɬi=ča
|
an
|
lapanaak
|
[yuu
|
maalaʔa̰čaa–kan–ɬi
|
ØOBJ ]
|
|
evid–go–pfv=cl
|
det
|
man
|
rel
|
send.X–indef.sub–pfv
|
__
|
|
‘The man that they
sent went.’
|
|
(MacKay and
Trechsel 2012: 111, line 12)
|
(50)
|
máatanahún
[yúu tawilánančáaɬ ʔa̰ɬmaʔá̰sɗá̰y]
|
|
maa–ta–nahun
|
[yuu
|
ta–wila–nan–čaaɬ
|
ØSUB
|
aɬmaʔast’ay]
|
|
evid–3pl.sub–tell
|
rel
|
3pl.sub–sitting–pl–there
|
__
|
up.there
|
|
‘Say those who live
in the North.’
|
|
(MacKay and
Trechsel 2012: 111, line 9)
|
Both
of these relatives, one subject-centred (50) and one objected-centred (49), are introduced by
yuu (glossed here as a relativizer to facilitate comparison),
which (50)
shows to be invariant for number. Judging from some unanalyzed examples in
MacKay and Trechsel (2010), Pisaflores may also have relative clauses
introduced by the determiner ʔan, though this remains to be
confirmed by further investigation.
In summary, then, Tepehua languages use determiners or elements
cognate with determiners to introduce both externally-headed and headless
relative clauses which can be centred on any type of object; the presence of
locative-centred relative clauses has only been substantiated for Huehuetla
Tepehua. There is no evidence for internally-headed constructions in any of
these languages, and all attested examples of relatives thus far follow
predicate-initial constituent order in the embedded clause.
The Totonac
branch of the family is somewhat larger and more ramified than the Tepehua
branch. In the sections below I will begin with the most divergent Totonac
language, Misantla, and then move on to the Central group, divided up into
Northern, Cerro Xinolatépetl, Filomeno Mata, Lowland, and Sierra subgroups.
Relatively
little is known about relative clauses in Misantla. While there is a very good
grammar of Misantla Totonac (MacKay 1999), this work is focused primarily on
the phonology and morphology of the language and does not touch at all on
relativization. There are, however, some unanalyzed examples in MacKay and
Trechsel (2005) that are given as translations of sentences that contain
relative clauses in Spanish. These are all externally-headed constructions and
most are introduced by an element glossed as a determiner in the texts in
MacKay and Trechsel (2012b), as in the example shown in (51):
|
Misantla Totonac
|
(51)
|
táštuɬ
hun čḭškúʔ [hun ikmaqníiniɬ ḭščičíʔ]
|
|
ta–štu–laɬ
|
hun
|
čḭškúʔ
|
[hun
|
ik–maqníi–ni–ɬ
|
ḭš–čičíʔ
|
Øobj]
|
|
inch–out–pfv
|
det
|
man
|
det
|
1sub–kill–dat–pfv
|
3poss–dog
|
__
|
|
‘The man whose dog
I killed came out.’
|
|
(MacKay and
Trechsel 2005: 225)
|
The
relative clause in (51) is centred on the applied object of the verb maqniini
‘X kills Y affecting Z’ licensed by the dative applicative -ni.
It not clear exactly what rank on the Accessibility Hierarchy to assign this
object, but MacKay and Trechsel (2008) argue that objects in Misantla are
symmetrical in the sense of Bresnan and Moshi (1990). Thus, presumably, if one
type of object can be relativized then they all can, and accessibility to
relativization extends at least as far down the hierarchy as the lowest-ranked
object. The determiner in this construction, hun,
is an obvious cognate of the Huehuetla Tepehua article huː.
There are also two examples of translations of Spanish sentences
with externally-headed relative clauses where the corresponding elements in
Misantla are not introduced by a determiner. If these are relative clauses,
one—shown in (52)—would be subject-centred, and the other object-centred:
|
Misantla Totonac
|
|
(52)
|
ikláːmin
hun čḭškúʔ [taqapḭ́ištá̰n]
|
|
|
ik–laː–min–na
|
hun
|
čḭškúʔ
|
[taqapḭ́i–šta̰n
|
ØSUB]
|
|
|
1sub–cmt–come–cmt
|
det
|
man
|
drunk–past
|
__
|
|
|
‘I come with the
man who was drunk.’
|
|
(MacKay and
Trechsel 2005: 152)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
There
is also a sentence in the text in MacKay and Trechsel (2012b: 140–141, line 90)
that could be a determiner-less subject-centred relative clause, though other
interpretations of the structure are possible. Another possibility is that
structures like that in (52) are in fact internally-headed relative clauses with a fronted
argument (cf. the Zapotitlán example in 93 below), a hypothesis which merits further investigation.
It appears from a single example in the text at the end of MacKay
(1999) that it may be possible to form headless relatives introduced by the
determiner as well:
|
Misantla Totonac
|
(53)
|
katačɔ́χɔɬčú
hɔ́n kíʔa̰ʔḭ́škiɬ ʔíɬáχaat
|
|
ka–ta–čuqu–la(ɬ)–ču
|
hun
|
kin–a̰–ḭški–la(ɬ)
|
iš–ɬaqaat
|
|
irr–inch–remain–pfv–cl
|
det
|
1obj–mom–giveXtoY–pfv
|
3poss–clothes
|
|
‘He is left
(behind), the one who lent me his clothes.’
|
|
(MacKay 1999: 447,
line 41)
|
However,
what appear to be headless relative clauses formed by a somewhat different
strategy are also attested in the text in MacKay and Trechsel (2012b):
|
Misantla Totonac
|
(54)
|
lakáːčukús
máːsiyṵ́štá̰n tuːt líːtapahánuːɬ
|
|
lakaː=ču–kus
|
maːsiyṵ–šta̰n
|
tuːt
|
lii–ta–pahanuː–la(ɬ)
|
|
neg=cl–still
|
tell.X–past
|
what
|
inst–inch–happen–pfv
|
|
‘He still did not
tell what it was that happened.’
|
|
(MacKay and
Trechsel 2012b: 156, line 164)
|
|
laː
kakíːlá̰χ kawá̰n túːpičú líːɬáːhaɬ
|
(55)
|
laː
|
ka–kiː–la̰qa̰n–ti
|
ka–wan
|
tuː–piʔ=ču
|
liː–ɬaːha–la(ɬ)
|
|
no
|
irr–intn–see.X–2sg:pfv
|
irr–say.X
|
what–maybe=cl
|
inst–earn.X–pfv
|
|
‘No, go see him so
that he might tell you what he earned (his riches) with.’
|
|
(MacKay and
Trechsel 2012b: 130–131, line 45)
|
If
these are indeed relative clauses, we have a headless subject-centred relative
clause in (54) and an (instrumental) object-centred construction in (55). Both are
introduced by tuː(t) ‘what’, the cognate of the
Upper Necaxa non-human relativizer. Thus, it seems possible that Misantla uses
different relativizers for externally-headed constructions (and, potentially,
internally-headed constructions if that is the correct interpretation of (52) above). However,
given that both of these examples here involve a matrix verb of speaking (maːsiyṵ
‘X recounts Y’ and wan ‘X says Y’), another possibility
is that we are looking at sentential complements of verbs in the form of “embedded
questions”—subordinate clauses introduced by interrogative words subcategorized
for by a certain class of verb. These would not be relative clauses in the
traditional sense in that they are not adnominal modifiers (a role filled in
Misantla by the determiner-headed constructions seen in (51) above), but it
seems like a very small step, both semantically and syntactically, between the
use of constructions like these in the more restrictive context (complement of
a specifc type of verb) to a less restricted use as an argument of verbs in
general, making them the functional equivalent of headless relative clauses in
sentences like the Upper Necaxa example in (18) above. Where exactly on this cline the
Misantla tuː-constructions are is still
uncertain. Even so, it does seem to be the case that Misantla occupies an
intermediate position between Tepehua, which makes exclusive use of a
determiner in relativization, and Upper Necaxa (and other Totonac languages, as
we’ll see below), which has taken an additional step and extended the use of tiː/tuː
to adnominal relative constructions. We will return to this issue in section 4.
Northern Totonac
The only member
of the Northern group of the Central Totonac branch of the family that has any
substantial amount of documentation yet, other than Upper Necaxa, is
Apapantilla.
Not unsurprisingly, relative clauses in this language closely resemble those in
Upper Necaxa, although the Apapantilla relativizers are a̰ntiː
and a̰ntuː. The examples in (56) and (57) show externally-headed relative clauses
with animate heads introduced by a̰ntiː:
|
Apapantilla Totonac
|
(56)
|
čiɬtsá̰
wan čḭškṵ́ [a̰ntiː tamaːwakṵtun kušḭ]
|
|
čin–ɬ=tsá̰
|
wan
|
čḭškṵ́
|
[a̰ntiː
|
tamaːwa–kṵtun
|
kušḭ
|
ØSUB]
|
|
arrive–pfv=now
|
det
|
man
|
hrel
|
buy–dsd
|
corn
|
__
|
|
‘The man who wants
to buy corn arrived.’
|
|
(Reid 1991: 58)
|
|
čiɬtsá̰
wan čḭškṵ́ [a̰ntiː ša̰ḭqa̰ɬiːma̰ː]
|
(57)
|
čin–ɬ=tsá̰
|
wan
|
čḭškṵ́
|
[a̰ntiː
|
ša̰–ḭk–qa̰ɬiː–ma̰ː
|
ØOBJ]
|
|
arrive–pfv=now
|
det
|
man
|
hrel
|
past–1sg.sub–wait–prog
|
__
|
|
‘The man who I am
waiting for arrived.’
|
|
(Reid 1991: 58)
|
The
example in (56) is subject-centred, while that in (57) is object-centred. (58) shows a
subject-centred headless relative clause introduced by a̰ntiː,
while (59)
shows an object-centred headless relative clause with an inanimate referent,
introduced by a̰ntuː:
|
Apapantilla Totonac
|
(58)
|
a̰nan
a̰ntiː lex tatsṵtsṵnun
|
|
a̰nan
|
[a̰ntiː
|
lex
|
ta–tsṵtsṵ–nun
|
ØSUB]
|
|
exist
|
hrel
|
much
|
3pl.sub–smoke–indef.obj
|
__
|
|
‘There are many who
smoke a lot.’
|
|
(Reid et al.,
n.d.)
|
|
ḭkpaːtsa̰nqaːɬ
[a̰ntuː kiwa̰nḭ]
|
(59)
|
ḭk–paːtsa̰nqaː–ɬ
|
[a̰ntuː
|
kin–wa̰n–nḭ
|
ØOBJ]
|
|
1sg.sub–forget–pfv
|
nrel
|
1obj–say–ben
|
__
|
|
‘I forgot what he
told me.’
|
|
(Reid 1991: 58)
|
The
relativizers here appear to be composed, at least etymologically, of tiː/tuː
and what was historically a deictic
element, *a̰n (cf. Upper Necaxa a̰n ‘medial non-demonstrative
determiner’).
Fronting of an argument within the relative clause is mentioned as a
possibility in Reid et al. (1968), where the following example is given:
|
Apapantilla Totonac
|
(60)
|
a̰ntiː
leːx ɬuːwa̰ tasaːkwa̰ ḭškaːmaːskuxma̰ː laqaliːyaːn]
|
|
[a̰ntiː
|
leːx
|
ɬuːwa̰
|
tasaːkwa̰
|
ḭš–kaː–maː–skux–ma̰ː
|
laqaliːyaːn
|
ØSUB]
|
|
[ hrel
|
much
|
many
|
peon
|
past–caus–work–prog
|
daily
|
__
|
|
‘the one who
employed very many peons daily’
|
|
(Reid et al. 1968:
47)
|
The
authors note that this type of fronting within a dependent clause is possible
when the fronted element is “emphasized” or the fronted element contains a
quantifier, as in (60) above. This seems in line with the Upper Necaxa data, where fronting in
the relative clause correlates with focalization.
While nothing is said explicitly in my sources about accessibility
to relativization, examples culled from the lexical database compiled by
missionaries from the Summer Institute of Linguistics (Reid et al., n.d.)
include locative-centred relative clauses introduced by a̰nɬaː ‘where’
(composed of *a̰n and ɬaː ‘where?’):
|
Apapantilla Totonac
|
(61)
|
ka̰ːliːxikwa̰ nak ka̰ːkḭwḭːn a̰nɬaː
wḭː misin
|
|
ka̰ː–liːxikwa̰
|
nak
|
ka̰ːkḭwḭːn
|
[a̰nɬaː
|
wḭː
|
misin
|
ØLOC]
|
|
plc–frightening
|
loc
|
jungle
|
locrel
|
sit
|
jaguar
|
__
|
|
‘In the jungle
where there there are jaguars (is) a frightening place.’
|
|
(Reid et al.,
n.d.)
|
There
are also attestations of possessor-centred relative clauses:
|
Apapantilla Totonac
|
(62)
|
maːqo̰šamišiːɬ wan puskaːt a̰ntiː
sputnḭɬ ḭškaman
|
|
maːqo̰šamišíː–ɬ
|
wan
|
puskaːt
|
[a̰ntiː
|
sput–nḭ–ɬ
|
ḭš–kaman
|
ØPOSS]
|
|
console–pfv
|
det
|
woman
|
hrel
|
finish–ben–pfv
|
3poss–child
|
__
|
|
‘He consoled the
woman whose child died.’
|
|
(Reid et al.,
n.d.)
|
So
it would seem that Apapantilla resembles Upper Necaxa in covering most of the Accessibility Hierarchy.
The remainder of
the Totonac languages fall into the South Central–Lowland division, which is
comprised by two large branches encompassing an undetermined number of
variants, Lowland and Sierra, and two individual languages, Cerro Xinolatépetl
and Filomeno Mata, which appear to be peripheral to either of these branches.
The most divergent of the two, Cerro Xinolatépetl, is virtually undescribed and
what information we have about relatives in this language comes from the text in
Andersen (2012), which contains two examples of relative clauses, one with an
animate external head (63), and the other a headless relative with an inanimate referent (64):
|
Cerro Xinolatépetl Totonac
|
|
(63)
|
ḭšya̰nán
ča̰ːtúm tá̰qo̰ː [tḭ́ː štɐwɐní lɑqóȼɐs]
|
|
|
ḭš–ya̰nán
|
ča̰ː–tum
|
tá̰qo̰ː
|
[tiːn
|
ḭš–ta–wan–ní
|
laqúȼas
|
ØOBJ]
|
|
past–arrive
|
clf–one
|
old.woman
|
hrel
|
past–3pl.sub–say–ben
|
Laqotsas
|
__
|
|
‘There was an old
woman they called “Laqotsas”.’
|
|
|
(Andersen 2012:
182, line 2)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
(64)
|
[tuː
ḭšyá̰ɬ] ɬkunḭːtʰȼá̰ː
|
|
[tuːn
|
ḭš–yá̰n–lḭ
|
ØSUB]
|
ɬkuyú–nḭːt=ȼá̰ː
|
|
nrel
|
past–go–pfv
|
__
|
burn–pf=now
|
|
‘The one who came
out burned up.’
|
|
(Andersen 2012:
193, line 47)
|
These
examples are, respectively, subject- (64) and object-centred (63), and make use of
tiːn and tuːn relativizers.
Filomeno Mata phonology and morphology are described in McFarland
(2009), but this work does not address relativization; however, several examples
of relative clauses do appear in the text in McFarland (2012). The example in (65) is an
externally-headed object-centred relative introduced by the non-human
relativizer, tuu= (analyzed by McFarland as a
clitic):
|
Filomeno Mata Totonac
|
|
(65)
|
tapuuwán
amá ⁿtíxi [ⁿtuušmaaštumáak …]
|
|
|
ta–puuwán
|
amá
|
tíxi
|
[tuu=š–maa–štu–maa–kan
|
ØOBJ]
|
|
3pl.sub–think
|
this
|
road
|
nrel=past–caus–out–prog–refl
|
__
|
|
‘They think, this
road that they were building …’
|
|
(McFarland 2012:
276, line 31)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
In (66) we see a headless
subject-centred relative clause with an animate referent:
|
Filomeno Mata Totonac
|
(66)
|
[tiištamaatɬaawaní
mákina]
|
|
[tii=iš–ta–maa–tɬaawan–nii
|
mákina
|
ØSUB]
|
|
hrel=past–3pl.sub–caus–walk–dat
|
machine
|
__
|
|
‘the ones who drove
the machines’
|
|
(McFarland 2012:
274, line 22)
|
(67) shows a headless
object-centred relative clause with an inanimate referent:
|
Filomeno Mata Totonac
|
(67)
|
[ⁿtuuškaamaqskíma
ʔamá ʔaqsqawiníʔi]
|
|
[tuu=š–kaa–maq–skin–maa
|
amá
|
aq–sqawi–níʔi
|
ØOBJ]
|
|
nrel=past–pl.obj–body–ask–prog
|
this
|
head–twist–agt
|
__
|
|
‘what this devil
asked them for’
|
|
(McFarland 2012:
275, line 34)
|
There
are also some examples of locative-centred relative clauses such as that in (68):
|
Filomeno Mata Totonac
|
(68)
|
paɾa
tsenatawašnán ʔamá ʔántsa ksípi [ɬaaštata ʔaqtseqóo mákina]
|
|
para
|
tsi–na–ta–waš–nan
|
amá
|
ántsa
|
k–sípi
|
|
if
|
well–fut–3pl.sub–dig–indef.obj
|
this
|
here
|
loc–hill
|
|
[ɬaa=š–ta–ta–aq–tsi–qoo
|
mákina
|
ØLOC]
|
|
locrel=past–3pl.sub–mid–head–hide–tot
|
machine
|
__
|
|
‘if they could dig
on that hill where the machines got stuck’
|
|
(McFarland 2012:
272, lines 11–12)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
The
relative clause here is introduced by the locative relativizer ɬaa=,
likely cognate with the relativizing element xa̰ː
used in the locative-centred relative clauses in Upper Necaxa in (36) and (37)above. In total, there are 31 instances of relative clauses in the text
in McFarland (2012) and while this is a very small sample on which to make
generalizations about constituent order, in all but one of the examples the
relativizing clitic attaches to a verbal or non-verbal predicate, and in one
case (p. 274, line 41) it attaches to an adverbial element glossed as ‘now’
preceding the verb, suggesting that there is at least a strong preference for
relatives clauses to be predicate-initial.
For the Lowland group, we have only information from Cerro del Carbón
(a.k.a. Papantla Totonac), once again gleaned from texts (Levy 2012). In this
language, we appear to find a structural distinction between externally-headed
and headless relative clauses. An externally-headed object-centred relative
clause is illustrated in (69):
|
Cerro del Carbón Totonac
|
(69)
|
amáː
sáqat [niːma kaːmaqštaqniːta̰]
|
|
amáː
|
sáqat
|
[niːma
|
kaː–maqštaq–niːtan–ʔ
|
ØPO]
|
|
that
|
tall.grass
|
rel
|
pl.obj–leave–pf–2sg.sub
|
__
|
|
‘that tall grass
that you left’
|
|
(Levy 2012: 355,
line 37)
|
The
head of the relative clause here is sáqat ‘tall grass’,
an inanimate noun; in (70) we see a subject-centred relative clause with a plural animate
head:
|
Cerro del Carbón Totonac
|
(70)
|
amáː
čḭškuwíːn [níːma ištalayáːna ištampíːn kḭ́wi] mat tawán …
|
|
amáː
|
čḭšku–wíːn
|
[niːma
|
iš–ta–layaː–na
|
ØSUB
|
|
that
|
man–pl
|
rel
|
past–3pl.sub–be.standing–st.pl
|
__
|
|
|
iš–tampíː–n
|
kḭwi]
|
mat
|
ta–wan–yaː
|
|
|
3poss–under–nmlzr
|
tree
|
qtv
|
3pl.sub–say.it–impf
|
|
‘The men that were
at the foot of the tree said …’
|
|
(Levy 2012: 392,
line 189)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
In
both examples, the relative clause is introduced by níːma,
which varies neither with the animacy nor the number of the head of the
relative construction. The texts contain 14 examples of externally-headed
relative clauses, all of which are subject- or object-centred, and in all of
which the relativizer immediately precedes the verb.
Headless relatives, on the other hand, use tuː
and tiː, as in (71) and (72):
|
Cerro del Carbón Totonac
|
(71)
|
…
išliːmín [tuː išqaːɬaniːt]
|
|
iš–liːmín
|
[tuː
|
iš–qaːɬán–niːtán
|
ØPO]
|
|
past–bring
|
nrel
|
past–steal–pf
|
__
|
|
‘… (each) brought
what he had stolen.’
|
|
(Levy 2012:
390–391, line 182)
|
(72)
|
…
tiː iškaːmaqpaːwaníːt
|
|
[tiː
|
iš–kaː–maq–paːwa–niːtán
|
ØPO]
|
|
nrel
|
past–pl.obj–caus–borrow–pf
|
__
|
|
‘… those from whom
he had borrowed.’
|
|
(Levy 2012: 417,
line 62)
|
Both
the examples here are object-centred, but a search through the 19 examples in
the texts reveals that there are subject-centred clauses as well as clauses
centred on what Levy (2002) analyses as secondary objects. All but one of the
examples, shown in (73), has the embedded verb in absolute clause-initial position:
|
Cerro del Carbón Totonac
|
(73)
|
qašmata
[tuː amáː kiɬwama conejo] mat ɬtḭːt tikšɬi amáː ušpi
|
|
qašmat–yaː
|
[tuː
|
amáː
|
kiɬ–wan–mah
|
conejo
|
ØPO]
|
mat
|
|
hear.it:1/3–impf
|
nrel
|
that
|
mouth–say.it–prog:1/3
|
rabbit
|
__
|
qtv
|
|
|
ɬtḭːt
|
tikš–li
|
amáː
|
ušpi
|
|
|
idph
|
fart–pfv
|
that
|
alligator
|
|
‘Hei
listens to what the rabbit is saying and, pbbt, the alligatori
farts.’
|
|
(Levy 2012: 464,
line 255)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
In (73), the verb kiɬwama
‘say something’ is preceded by a demonstrative amáː
‘that’; however, it isn’t entirely clear what the role of the demonstrative is
in this sentence. One possibility is that it expresses the object (what the
rabbit is saying), in which case this is an example of an internally-headed
relative clause. Another possibility is that tuː amáː
functions as a unit, forming a demonstrative relativizer. This is an
interesting example and structures like these clearly merit further
investigation.
For the Sierra group, there are a few examples of relative clauses
from Olintla Totonac found in the text in Tino (2012). On the whole, these
resemble the Northern Totonac pattern found in Upper Necaxa and Apapantilla, in
which both externally-headed and headless relative clauses are introduced by a
relativizer that varies according to animacy. Externally-headed constructions
are illustrated in (74) and (75):
|
Olintla Totonac
|
(74)
|
…
ⁿtɘˈmaː liɑˈqɑmaːni maː [ˈⁿtu maːʃˈkeːka] ˈqɔtwɘɬ
|
|
tamáː
|
liː–qámaːn
|
i
|
maː
|
[tu
|
maːʃkéː–ka
|
ØOBJ]
|
qút–wa–ɬi
|
|
that
|
inst–play
|
jnct
|
ptcl
|
nrel
|
give–indef.sub:pfv
|
__
|
drink–eat–pfv
|
|
‘….he swallowed the
toy that they gave him.’
|
|
(Tino 2012: 299,
line 14)
|
(75)
|
ˈsqɑta̰Ɂ
ˈⁿtʃo [ⁿtiː ɑqɑmaːˈnɘni] …
|
|
sqátaɁ
|
tʃo
|
[ti
|
qamaːnán
|
ØSUB
|
i]
|
|
baby
|
ptcl
|
hrel
|
play:impf
|
__
|
jnct
|
|
‘… the baby that
was playing …’
|
|
(Tino 2012: 308,
line 41)
|
These
examples depart slightly from patterns we’ve seen previously in that the head
noun is separated from the relativizer, tu
or ti, by elements glossed as “particles”; however, there
are other examples in the text where the head noun is immediately adjacent to
the relativizer (e.g., p. 309, line 42; p. 310, line 63). Note that we have
both subject- (75) and object-centred (74) relative clauses here in these examples.
Headless relatives introduced by tu
and ti are also attested:
|
Olintla Totonac
|
(76)
|
ˈpus ˈⁿtʃo nɘˈtluwja [ˈⁿtu kuniˈjaːn]
|
|
pus
|
tʃo
|
na–tluwá–jaː–Ɂ
|
[tu
|
k–wan–ni–jáː–n
|
ØOBJ]
|
|
well
|
ptcl
|
fut–make–impf–2sg.sub
|
nrel
|
1sg.sub–say–ben–impf–2obj
|
__
|
|
‘Well then you’ll
do what I say.’
|
|
(Tino 2012: 314,
line 56)
|
(77)
|
ˈpiː
ˈniː ˈniː niːˈto aˈnɘni ˈᵐpe ˈlaːntla [ˈⁿti ˈⁿtlaːn ʃtaːtʃuˈwinɘɬ]
|
|
piː
|
niː
|
niː
|
niːtó
|
anán
|
i
|
pe
|
láːntlaɁ
|
|
since
|
neg
|
neg
|
neg
|
be
|
jnct
|
since
|
how
|
|
|
[ti
|
tlaːn
|
ʃ–taː–tʃuwínan–ɬi
|
ØOBJ]
|
|
|
hrel
|
well
|
past–cmt–speak–pfv
|
__
|
|
‘Since no, no,
there was no one that she could talk with.’
|
|
(Tino 2012: 300,
line 16)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Both
of these examples are object-centred. Example (77) is of note in that it shows the embedded
verb preceded by an adverbial, tlaːn ‘well’, which is the source of
the ‘could’ in the translation. This indicates that Olintla, like Huehuetla
Tepehua and Upper Necaxa, preserves the pre-verbal positioning of adverbial
elements inside relative clauses.
The nearby language of Huehuetla Totonac is described in Troiani
(2004), which does not address relativization directly but provides a few
examples in texts. Only headless relative clauses are attested at all for this
language, and these make use of the tu and ti
relativizers. Examples (78) illustrates a headless relative with an inanimate referent:
|
Huehuetla Totonac
|
(78)
|
paks
maqɬtimán [tuku kiɬwámpaːt]
|
|
paks
|
maqɬti–ma–n
|
[tu–ku
|
kiɬ–wan–paːt
|
ØOBJ]
|
|
all
|
remove–impf–2obj
|
nrel–still
|
lips–say–impf:2sg.sub
|
__
|
|
‘She’s taking away
from you everything that you are saying.’
|
|
(Troiani 2004:
128, line 18)
|
Of
note in example (78) is the combination of the relativizer with the suffix (most likely
a clitic in morphosyntactic terms) -ku ‘still’ (Fr. ‘encore’).
The corresponding element in Upper Necaxa, =kus,
is not attested in combination with the relativizers, though it combines with a
wide range of other elements. While most of the examples in these texts show
the relativizer combining with -ku, examples like (79) show that this is
not obligatory:
|
Huehuetla Totonac
|
|
(79)
|
…
maqkatsíy [tu lilaqatalawilikaníːt ktsiʔ]
|
|
|
maq–katsí–y
|
[tu
|
liː–laqa–tála–wíla–i–kan–niːta
|
š–tsiʔ
|
ØOBJ]
|
|
caus–know–asp
|
hrel
|
inst–front–jam–sit–trns–sub.supp–pf
|
3poss–mother
|
__
|
|
‘… he went to find
out what his mother had been shut inside with.’
|
|
|
(Troiani 2004:
135, line 27)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
The
relative clause here has an inanimate referent, the knowledge of the Actor in
the matrix clause. The example in (80) illustrates a headless relative clause with an animate referent:
|
Huehuetla Totonac
|
(80)
|
tsukúka
kiːkškanáči [tikú maːstawaníka], kawása tɬawakaníːt
|
|
tsúku–kan–ɬ
|
kiː–ukšíɬ–kan–ya–či
|
[ti–ku
|
|
begin–sub.supp–aor
|
dir–see–sub.supp–asp–here
|
hrel–still
|
|
|
maː–stakwa–ni–kan–ɬ
|
ØOBJ
|
kawása
|
tɬáwa–kan–niːta
|
|
|
caus–wake.up–appl–sub.supp–aor
|
__
|
boy
|
make–sub.supp–pf
|
|
‘They began to come
see the one that had been given life, a boy had been made.’
|
|
(Troiani 2004:
147, line 17)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
The
second clause at the end of this example, kawása tɬawakaníːt,
is glossed in the original as a relative clause ‘the boy that has been made’
but is set off from the rest of the utterance by a prosodic boundary (“//”)
which I’ve represented in the transcription line as a comma; however, there is
no relativizer in the Totonac and the indefinite actors in the first clause
(the unspecified group that is coming to see the boy) and the final clause (the
unspecified actor that made the boy) are not the same, whereas identity of
unspecified actors would be expected within the confines of a single sentence.
The possibility remains that this is indeed a paratactic relative construction
of the type seen in Misantla in (52), although to date no further evidence that this structure might
exist in Huehuetla Totonac, or any other Sierra or Central Totonac language,
has been found.
Turning to the Totonac spoken in Ozelonacaxtla, we find half a dozen
examples of relative clauses in the text in Román Lobato (2012). These show the
familiar Sierra pattern of externally-headed and headless relatives introduced
by relativizers that distinguish the animacy of the head of the relative
clause, although the relativizers have a slightly different form. The inanimate
relativizer (81) is given as tuku (cf. the Huehuetla form in (78) above), while the
animate relativizer is titʃi (82):
|
Ozelonacaxtla Totonac
|
(81)
|
…
milḭwti [tuku putsapa̰ːt]
|
|
mi–liwa̰t
|
i
|
[tuku
|
putsa–pa̰ːt
|
ØPO]
|
|
2poss–food
|
jnct
|
nrel
|
look.for–progː2sg.sub
|
__
|
|
‘the food that you
are looking for’
|
|
(Román Lobato
2012: 329, line 31)
|
(82)
|
pus
mat ˈwa̰nitʃu tḭˈma̰ː tʃiʃˈkṵː [ˈtitʃi ˈkskuhmah] …
|
|
pus
|
mat
|
wa̰ni=tʃu
|
tḭma̰ː
|
tʃiʃkṵ
|
ṵ
|
[titʃi
|
k–skuh–maah
|
ØSUB]
|
|
will
|
qtv
|
say=ptcl
|
dist
|
hombre
|
jnct
|
hrel
|
past–work–prog
|
__
|
|
‘Well, he said to
the man that was working …’
|
|
(Román Lobato
2012: 331, line 39)
|
There
is currently not enough data to determine if these are actually unanalyzed
combinations of a relativizer and some other element, as we saw in Huehuetla
Totonac, or if these are in fact fixed forms derived diachronically from such
sources.
The examples in (81) and (82) are object- and subject-centred, respectively. It also appears from
an example given in Román Lobato (2008) that possessor-centred relatives are
possible:
|
Ozelonacaxtla Totonac
|
(83)
|
ni paɾ wáːču liːtalaqa̰putsíču čiškúː
[tíčiː špuskáːti šwánt]
|
|
ni
|
paɾ
|
wáː=ču
|
liː–ta–laqa̰putsí=ču
|
čiškú-u
|
[tiči–i
|
|
neg
|
if
|
foc=cl
|
inst–inch–worry=cl
|
man–jnct
|
hrel–jnct
|
|
|
š–puskáːt–i
|
ØPOSS
|
š–wa–nḭt]
|
|
|
3poss–woman–jnct
|
__
|
past–be–pf
|
|
‘The man whose wife
she was also didn’t get into trouble.’
|
|
(Román Lobato
2008: 67)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
This
is an interesting example because the target of relativization is the possessor
of the complement of the copular verb rather than of its argument.
Of particular note in the Ozelonacaxtla data is the following
example, in which it appears that one of the arguments of the embedded clause
intervenes between the verb and the relativizer:
|
Ozelonacaxtla Totonac
|
(84)
|
…
špuskaːti [titʃi wa̰ʝa̰ tla̰wkah]
|
|
š–puskaːti
|
[titʃi
|
wa̰ʝa̰
|
tla̰wa–kah
|
ØPO]
|
|
3poss–woman
|
hrel
|
hawk
|
make–indef.sub
|
__
|
|
‘… the wife of the
one they turned into a hawk.’
|
|
(Román Lobato
2012: 341, line 90)
|
In (84) we see that the
noun wa̰ʝa̰ ‘hawk’, the object of the verb tla̰wa
‘X makes Y into Z’,
immediately follows the relativizer titʃi, separating
it from the verb. This would appear to be an example of argument fronting
inside the relative clause, although another possibility is that wa̰ʝa̰
‘hawk’ here is not an ordinary object but some kind of predicate complement
occupying the pre-verbal slot normally taken by secondary predicates. This will
have to remain an open question, pending further investigation.
Relative clauses in Zapotitlán Totonac (sometimes referred to in the
literature as “Sierra” or “Highland Totonac”) are described in an article by E.
Aschmann (1984), although the scope of that paper and the range of
constructions discussed under the heading of “relative clause” is somewhat
broader than ours is here. Drawing on the descriptions in this paper and on
unanalyzed examples contained in the lexical database compiled by H. Aschmann
(n.d.a), it can be seen that Zapotitlán strongly resembles the other Sierra
languages in most respects. Externally-headed relatives are introduced by tiː
and tuː relativizers that distinguish animacy, and may be subject-
(85) or
object-centred (86):
|
Zapotitlán Totonac
|
(85)
|
…
sqa̰ta̰ wa̰ː [ⁿtiː taqalanaː lakáčiɬ]
|
|
sqa̰ta̰
|
wa̰ː
|
[tiː
|
taqalanaː
|
laka–čin–ɬ
|
ØSUB]
|
|
baby
|
that.one
|
hrel
|
with.difficulty
|
face–arrive.here–pfv
|
__
|
|
‘… a baby that was
born with great difficulty’
|
|
(H. Aschmann,
n.d.a)
|
(86)
|
lḭya̰nqo̰ːy
šmuɾaːɬka̰n wa̰ː [ⁿtuː ᵐpuːmuhuːqo̰ːy šliːšqatna̰ka̰n]
|
|
lḭya̰n–qo̰ː–y
|
š–muɾaːɬ–ka̰n
|
wa̰ː
|
[tuː
|
puːmuhuː–qo̰ː–y
|
|
take–3pl–impf
|
3poss–bag–pl.po
|
that.one
|
nrel
|
put.into–3pl–impf
|
|
|
š–liːšqatna̰–ka̰n
|
ØOBJ]
|
|
|
3poss–stake–pl.po
|
__
|
|
‘They take along
their shoulder bags in which they put their stakes.’
|
|
(E. Aschmann 1984:
20)
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Of
particular note in these constructions is the presence of the element wa̰ː
intervening between the head noun and the relativizer. This is an extremely
frequent feature of relative constructions in Zapotitlán, so much so that H.
Aschmann (n.d.a) analyzes the relativizers as wa̰ːntiː
and wa̰ːntuː, respectively; however, there are examples (see (92) below) where the
relativizer appears without wa̰ː, and in E. Aschmann’s (1984)
article wa̰ː is treated as a separate focus particle. Comparison
with probable cognates in other Totonacan languages shows that this element is
likely derived from a demonstrative element of some kind.
E. Aschmann’s article also provides examples of locative-centred (87) and
possessor-centred