Volume 11 Issue 1 (2013)
DOI:10.1349/PS1.1537-0852.A.436
Note: Linguistic Discovery uses Unicode characters
to represent phonetic symbols. Please see Optimizing Display
for requirements to accurately reproduce this page.
Object Markers in IkalangaRose Letsholo University of Botswana There is an on-going debate amongst linguists regarding the
status of the object marker (OM). Some scholars argue that OMs are agreement
morphology (Baker 2010, Riedel 2009) while others argue that OMs are pronominal
and not agreement morphology (Nevins 2010, Kramer, under review, Labelle 2007,
Demuth & Johnson 1990, Mchombo 2002). The purpose of this paper is to
contribute to this debate using data from Ikalanga to support the view that OMs
are pronominal clitics. I discuss evidence in favor of the agreement analysis as
well as that in favor of the pronominal analysis. OMs in Ikalanga behave like
agreement morphology in that they attach only to the verbal stem, only one OM
occurs in a clause, and they share grammatical features (person, gender and
number) with the lexical NP with which they co-refer. However, there are many
ways in which OMs behave like pronominals. For example, OMs do not vary in form
according to the mood of a sentence or negation while subject markers, which I
analyze as agreement morphemes do. They are not obligatory in Ikalanga sentences
while subject markers are. OMs are not subject to locality constraints while
agreement is. They can be bound by the subject (backward pronominalization),
something unexpected of agreement and there is ample evidence to show that the
lexical NP with which the OM co-refers is an adjunct, a fact which has been used
in the literature to argue that the OM is pronominal in such a set up. The
evidence in favor of the pronominal analysis however, is more compelling and
therefore I conclude that OMs are pronominal clitics and not agreement
morphology. 1. IntroductionA vast amount of literature exists on the topic of object
markers in languages of the world and in Bantu languages in particular. Most
papers that have been written on this subject investigate the status of the OM
in these languages e.g. Kramer (under review), Baker (2011), Hyman & Duranti
(1982), Bresnan and Mchombo (1987), Demuth & Johnson (1990) Siedl &
Dimitriadis 1997, Keach (1995) while others investigate the general
characteristics of OMs in Bantu e.g. Marten and Kula (ms.), Riedel (2009) with
the hope of finding some generalizations that cut across this language group.
While there are some interesting similarities in OMs across Bantu languages, it
is nevertheless a fact that OMs behave differently in different Bantu languages.
For example, in some languages OM is sometimes obligatory with lexical object
NPs - these languages include Swahili, Chaga and Saamba (Riedel 2009). In such
languages, OM has been analyzed as an agreement marker. In other languages, e.g
Chichewa, Zulu, and Sesotho, OM co-occurs only with dislocated object NPs. In
these languages, OM has been analyzed as an incorporated pronoun (e.g. Bresnan
& Mchombo 1987, Labelle 2007, Demuth & Johnson 1990, Mchombo 2002, Siedl
& Dimitriadis 1997 Hyman & Duranti 1982). Because of its inconsistent
behavior, it has been difficult for scholars investigating this topic to make a
generalization regarding the syntactic status of the OM in terms of whether it
is an agreement marker or some kind of pronoun. In the quest for uniformity of
analysis of this phenomenon, Riedel (2009) proposes that all OMs in Bantu
languages are agreement markers. I will argue against this view in this paper
using data from Ikalanga, one of the minority languages spoken in Botswana, to
support my arguments. This paper aims at making a contribution to this debate.
The main question that this paper investigates therefore is 'What is the status
of the OM in Ikalanga?' The rest of this paper is organized as follows: Section 2 provides
background information on the Ikalanga language while section 3 discusses the
theoretical framework adopted in this paper. Section 4 discusses evidence in
favor of the agreement analysis in Ikalanga while section 5 presents evidence in
favor of the pronominal analysis. Section 6 provides the conclusion. 2. Background2.1 Ikalanga word order
factsIkalanga (S16) is a Bantu language spoken in parts of
Botswana and parts of Zimbabwe (it is one of the minority languages in both
countries). It is basically an SVO language (example 1a) although arguments can
occur in a position other than their canonical position as illustrated in
(1b). (1a) | Néó | wá-ka-bíká | nya:ma[1]. |
| Neo1a | SA1-PST-cook | meat9 |
| 'Neo cooked/is cooking meat' |
(1b) | Wá-ka-bíká | nya:ma, | Neo. |
| SA1-PST-cook | meat9 | Neo1a |
| ‘She cooked the meat, Neo.’ (VOS) |
Ikalanga is a pro-drop language. Consider example
(2). (2) | Wá-ka-bóná | mbísá:na. |
| SA1-PST-see | boy1 |
| ‘She/He saw a boy'. |
The data in (2) shows that (2) can be interpreted to mean
'He/she saw a boy'. Without going into any specifics of determining the status
of the SA, in this paper, I will assume that the SA is an agreement morpheme
which agrees with a null subject pro (see Letsholo 2004 for further discussion
of this phenomenon). Before any further discussion of the OM in Ikalanga, I
first describe verbal extensions found in the language and then provide the
theoretical assumptions that will be used to analyze the data in this paper in
section 3. 2.2 The verb in
IkalangaThe verb in Ikalanga comprises of the verb root (VR) which
hosts (suffixal) extensions such as those shown in example (3): (3a) | applicative | bumb-il-a | (build for) | (3b) | causative | bumb-is-a | (cause to build) | (3c) | reciprocal | bumb-an-a | (build each other) | (3d) | passive | bumb-iw-a | (to be built) | (3e) | (a+b+c) | bumb-is-an-il-a | (cause to build for each other) |
In addition, the verb in Ikalanga also has prefixal elements
which encode information about agreement with the subject, tense/aspect, object
marker, negation and modality. These are illustrated in the examples in (4)
below[2]. The different morpheme
combinations that are affixed to the verb are indicated in brackets in examples
(4a-d) below. (4a) | Néó | wá- ka- bón-á | mbísá:na. |
| Neo1a | SA1- PST see-FV | boy1 |
| 'Neo saw a boy'. (SA+Tense + VR+ FV) |
(4b) | Néó | wá- ka-m -bó:n-a | mbísána. |
| Neo1a | SA1 PST-OM1- see-FV | boy1 |
| 'Neo saw him, the boy'. (SA+Tense + OM+ VR+ FV) |
(4c) | Néó | a-á- zo-m- bó:n-a | mbísá na. |
| Neo1a | NEG.-SM1 -PST-OM1 -see-FV | boy1 |
| 'Neo did not see him, the boy'.
(NEG.+SA+Tense+OM+VR+FV) |
(4d) | Néó | a-é- zh-á, | Nchídzí | ú-noo m -bó:n-a. |
| Neo1a | COND.-SA1-come -FV | Nchidzi1 | SA1-PRS.-OM1-see-FV |
| 'If Neo comes, Nchidzi will see her/him'.
(Cond+SM+VR+FV) |
3. Theoretical
AssumptionsCentral to the analysis adopted in this paper is the notion
of agree proposed in Chomsky (2000, 2001). Agree is a
relation established in the syntax between a functional head and a DP. In this
theory, a functional head that has un-interpretable features probes within its
c-command domain for a DP (goal) which has matching features. If such a DP with
matching un-interpretable features is found, then such a DP enters into an Agree
relation with the probe and checks its un-interpretable features. Agreement is
governed by locality restrictions, for example there cannot be an intervening NP
between the functional head which is the probe and the goal, that is the NP with
matching features. That said, Chomsky (2001) raises the possibility that
agreement can hold in non-local configurations. However, in this paper I adopt
the conception of agreement where it is a local configuration because to the
best of my knowledge agreement relations in Ikalanga are strictly local.
Further, I assume that vP has EPP features which necessitate object shift
but that in Ikalanga object shift is covert in non-specific DPs and overt for
specific DPs. In addition, I assume that adjunction can occur to the right or
to the left of the tree. For example, I assume that right adjunction is
responsible for the derivation of English sentences such as ‘I saw a
picture yesterday of the man I met at the store’. In addition, I appeal to
theta theory where relevant to explain phenomena in Ikalanga. Before putting
forth my proposed analysis of object markers in Ikalanga, I briefly discuss
recent analyses of similar phenomena in other languages, pointing out why these
anslyses cannot be adopted for Ikalanga. Nevins (2010) analyzes object markers as pronominal clitics which form
part of a big DP structure. In this analysis, the clitic starts off adjoined to
the doubled DP before it moves to spec vP where it undergoes m-merger
with v per Matushansky (2006). Clitic movement to spec vP is
regarded as object shift triggered by an EPP feature on v and licensed by
an agree relation. This structure is shown in (5) below:
(5a)
(5b) after DP/D movement and m-merger A modified version of this analysis is proposed in Kramer
(under review)[3] which she refers to
as the copy analysis of object markers. This analysis is similar to the Nevins
analysis discussed above in every respect with the exception that under this
analysis there is no separate DP/D clitic adjoined to the doubled DP. In this
analysis, v agrees with the DP which then moves to spec vP. The DP
then m-merges with v and the clitic adjoins to v. According to
Kramer, both copies of the doubled DP are pronounced (Kramer, under review:
26). While both of these analyses are interesting and nicely capture the
relationship between the OM and the lexical NP with which it co-refers, neither
of them can be adopted for Ikalanga (without modification) for different
reasons. Both Nevins adjunction analysis and Kramer's copy analysis could
potentially work for Ikalanga (with modifications that call for stipulations)
putting aside the adjunction analysis shortcomings which are clearly articulated
in Kramer. However, there are two main problems that both of these analyses seem
to pose with regards to the Ikalanga data. The first one is that in both of
these analyses, it is not clear from the authors' discussions whether the
lexical object NP that co-occurs with the OM is an adjunct in the languages
discussed and the structures proposed in both analyses do not suggest that this
is the case. In Ikalanga, as I will argue below, the lexical object NP that
co-occurs with the OM is not part of the VP. Secondly, the structure proposed in
Kramer produces the wrong word order for Ikalanga. Thus, because of these
shortcomings, I cannot adopt their big DP analysis without any
modification. There are two possible analyses that could work for Ikalanga and I
discuss each of them below. The first proposal is that the OM is a clitic which
occupies the D head of DP and that the lexical DP orginates as a complement of D
but is then adjoined to some functional category on the right as shown in (6)
below. The adjunction analysis proposed below is consistent with analyses
proposed for English sentences such as 'I thought for a very long time that
somebody would come' where the clause 'that somebody would come is extraposed to
the right (Collins, p.c.).
(6) This analysis has the advantage that it captures the
relationship between the clitic and lexical NP with which it co-refers. The
problem with this structure is that it requires that we stipulate the existence
of some functional projection FP, to which the lexical NP can adjoin. Secondly,
one is hard-pressed to justify the reason for the movement of the adjoined DP
since movement in minimalism is motivated by feature checking. In addition, this
analysis might be a problem if one adopts Kayne (1994) since this structure
violates antisymmetry. Due to the shortcomings discussed above, I propose an analysis in which
the lexical DP which co-refers with the OM is base generated to the right in the
tree diagram. The analysis I adopt in this paper is not widely used in the
literature. That notwithstanding, I find that this analysis best accounts for
the Ikalanga data as well as the data found in other Bantu languages such as
Chichewa and Zulu. First and foremost, consonant with others who have
investigated OMs (Bresnan & Mchombo (1987), Nevins (2010), Kramer (under
review and many others) I analyze Ikalanga OMs as pronominal clitics and not
agreement markers. Following the big DP analysis, I propose that in sentences in
which the OM occurs, the verb takes a null DP complement with the pronominal
clitic DP/D in the specifier of this DP. Unlike in the big DP analysis, I assume
that the lexical object DP is adjoined to VP and not itself a complement of V.
Secondly, I assume that the complement DP of V containing the OM undergoes
object shift to spec vP to check the EPP feature of v and that
OM undergoes m-merger with the verb at PF. The structure that results is
shown in (7) below.
(7)
This analysis has the disadvantage that it does not capture
the relationship between the lexical NP with which the OM co-refers since this
NP is base generated as an adjunct. However, the analysis has the advantage that
it captures the fact that the lexical NP is an adjunct and is outside VP as the
evidence presented below indicates. The analysis also has the advantage that it
captures the specificity interpretation of sentences in which the OM occurs. I
now turn to the debate regarding whether the OM is agreement or a pronominal
clitic in Ikalanga. I first present arguments which suggest that the OM in
Ikalanga is agreement and then present arguments which favor the pronominal
clitic analysis. 4. Object Markers as
AgreementWhile the position I take in this paper is that object
markers are pronominal clitics and not agreement morphology, there is
nonetheless some evidence to suggest that OMs might be agreement morphology in
Ikalanga. Such evidence include the position of the OM in relation to the verbal
stem, the number of OMs per clause and the fact that OMs share phi features with
the lexical NPS with which they co-refer. 4.1 Position in relation to
verbal stemThe OM in Ikalanga attaches only to the verbal stem (ex 8a)
and not to any other element such as auxiliaries or other hosts as do clitics in
Indo-European languages such as Romanian (9). Attaching an OM to say, an
auxiliary verb in Ikalanga results in ungrammaticality as evident from the
ungrammaticality of (8b). (8a) | Nchídzí | ú- nga- m-bó:n-a |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1- OM1-Aux- -see-FV |
| 'Nchidzi can see him/her. (OM = 3rd person singular, class
1) |
(8b) | *Nchídzí | ú m-nga bó:n-a |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-OM1-Aux-see-FV |
| 'Nchidzi can see him/her. (OM = 3rd person singular, class 1) |
(9) | I-am | vazut | pe | Popescu. |
| him-have-I | seen | to | Popescu |
| 'I have seen Popescu'. (Torrego 1995:Ex. 3b) |
In the Romanian example (9), the clitic 'I' (him) attaches
to the auxiliary 'am' (have). 4.2 Only one OM per
clauseThe OM also behaves like agreement morphology in that only
one OM occurs per clause even though it is possible to have more than one
internal object in the language. Consider the following example: (10a) | Nchídzí | wá-ka-bík-íl-á | mmé | nyá:ma. |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST-cook-APPL-FV | mother2 | meat9 |
| 'Nchidzi cooked meat for my mother'. |
(10b) | ?Nchídzí | wá-
ka-í-bá-bík-íl-á. |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST-
OM9-OM‑2-cook-APPL-FV |
| 'Nchidzi cooked meat for my mother'. (N.B The sentence remains
questionable even if we were to reverse the order of the OMs) |
Although the occurrence of two OMS in the same clause is
generally frowned at by speakers, there are some constructions where speakers
judgments of these are positive. Consider the following: (11) | Nchídzí | wá- ka-í-n-túmíl-íl-á.
|
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST- OM9-OM‑1-send-APPL-FV
|
| 'Nchidzi sent it to him/her' |
In languages that have pronominal clitics such as Spanish,
both the direct and indirect object can cliticize in the same clause as evident
in Spanish example (12). (12) | Se la | presentaron | (a ella) | (al profesor) |
| him-her | introduced | (to her) | (to the professor) |
| 'They introduced her to the professor'. (Torrego 1995: Ex.
17) |
The fact that examples such as (11) are judged possible by
some speakers weakens the argument for OMs as agreement in Ikalanga because
although these structures are not commonly used in everyday conversation, it
might not necessarily be due to the fact that they are ungrammatical. 4.3 OM shares phi features with
lexical NPAnother argument that could be used in favor of the
agreement analysis is that the OM, like other pronominals shares grammatical
features with the NP that it is anaphorically linked with: that is person,
gender and number. For example, in (13b) the OM is m- consonant with the
grammatical features of noun class 1, that is third person singular human.
Similarly the OM in example (13d) takes the grammatical features of class 7
which are third person singular non-human. Notice that the SA, which I analyze
as agreement morphology also takes these same features. Be that as it may,
notice that the subject marker wa- and the OM have distinct forms even
though they both carry similar grammatical features namely 3rd person
singular noun class 1; u (u-a in past tense) for
subject agreement and m- for object markers. Thus, the fact that they
have distinctive forms is suggestive of the fact that they are different
phenomena. (13a) | Nchídzí | wá- ka - bón-á | mbísá:na. |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST- see-FV | boy |
| Nchidzi saw a boy. |
(13b) | Nchídzí | wá ka m-bó:n-a | mbísána. |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST- OM1-see-FV | boy1 |
| 'Nchidzi saw him, the boy'. (OM = 3rd person singular, class
1) |
(13c) | Nchídzí | wá - ka - bón-á | chíbúlú:lu |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST- see-FV | lizard7 |
| 'Nchidzi saw a lizard'. |
(13d) | Nchídzí | wá - ka- chí-bó:n-á | chíbúlúlu |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1 -PST-OM7 see-FV | lizard7 |
| 'Nchidzi saw it, the lizard'. (OM=3rd person singular, class 7)
|
One of the features used to argue for OM as agreement
morphology in the literature is its inability to reference the theme NP (Kramer,
Baker 2010). The explanation given for this restriction is the locality
condition of agreement relations; that is, the goal argument is the one that can
agree with the OM because they are in the same domain. In Ikalanga however, both
the goal and the theme NP can cliticize to the verb. Consider the examples
below: (14a) | Nchídzí | wá ka-kér-él-á | Néo | bá:na. |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST-cut hair-APPL-FV | Neo1 | children2 |
| 'Nchidzi cut the children's hair on behalf of Neo'. |
(14b) | Nchídzí | wá ka-ba-kér-él-á | Né:o, | bá:na. |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST- OM2-cut hair-APPL-FV | Neo1 | children |
| 'Nchidzi cut it, the children's hair, on behalf of Neo'. |
(14c) | Nchídzí | wá ka-n-kér-él-á | bá:na | Né:o |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST- OM1-cut hair-APPL-FV | children2 | Neo1 |
| 'Nchidzi cut the children's hair on behalf of her, Neo. |
The agreement analysis predicts that the highest argument of
the two internal arguments will always be the one that takes an OM. However, in
Ikalanga both internal arguments of the verb are allowed to cliticize to the
verb; the theme argument as shown in (14b) and the goal argument as shown in
(14c). This further weakens the agreement analysis because according to the
Agree architecture outlined above, there should be no intervening NP with
matching features between the probe, v and the goal, which in this case
is the NP ngwana 'child'. Thus the agreement analysis predicts that such
an example should be ungrammatical, and it is not. Therefore, although there is
evidence that the OM might be agreement morphology, such evidence is not very
compelling. In the next section I present arguments in favor of OMs as
pronominal clitics. 5. Object Markers as Pronominal
CliticsThere is ample evidence in favor of analyzing OMs as
pronominal clitics. Such evidence is morpho-syntactic, syntactic, and semantic
in nature. I begin by presenting the morphosyntactic evidence before turning to
the syntactic and finally the semantic evidence. 5.1 Morpho-syntactic
evidenceInteraction with mood and
negationIt has been observed in the literature that while agreement
morphology varies due to the interaction with phenomena such as modality and
negation, OMs are invariant with these phenomena (Nevins 2010, Kramer, Mullen
1986). In this paper, I distinguish between the SA, which I analyze as agreement
morphology and the OM, which is a pronominal. Consider the following
examples: (15a) | Nchídzí | ú- no - bón-á | mbísá:na |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PRS-see-FV | boy |
| 'Nchidzi sees a boy'. |
(15b) | Nchídzí | a-á zo- bón-á | mbísá:na |
| Nchidzi1a | NEG-SA1-PST- see-FV | boy |
| 'Nchidzi did not see a boy'. |
(15c) | Nchídzí | a-é zhá:, | Néó | ú-noo tí:zha. |
| Nchidzi1a | COND.-SA1 -comes | Neo | SA1-FUT-run away |
| 'If Nchidzi comes, Neo will run away'. |
The subject agreement marker varies in form in the sentences
above: (15a) is just a simple declarative in the present tense, and the form of
the SA is u-, (15b) is a negative form of the sentence and the SA
is a- and (15c) is a conditional sentence and the form of the SA
is e-. Now consider the following examples involving OM. (16a) | Nchídzí | ú - no - m-bó:n-á | mbísána. |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PRS-OM-see-FV | boy |
| 'Nchidzi sees the boy'. (Simple declarative) |
(16b) | Nchídzí | a-á zo- m-bó:n-á | mbísána. |
| Nchidzi1a | NEG-SA1-PST-OM-see-FV | boy |
| 'Nchidzi did not see the boy'. (Negation) |
(16c) | Nchídzí | a-é zhá:, | Néó | ú-noo n-tí:zha. |
| Nchidzi1a | COND.-SA1 -comes | Neo | SA1-FUT-OM1-run away from |
| 'If Nchidzi comes, Neo will run away from him'.(Conditional) |
(16d) | Ú-ngá | n-thámíl-á | tí:ɪ? |
| SA1p.sing.-can | OM1-make-FV | tea |
| ‘Can he/she make tea for him/her. (Jussive) |
(16e) | ú-n--thámíl-é | tí:ɪ. |
| SA2p.sing-make-SUBJ. | tea |
| ‘Make tea for him. (Imperative) |
In all the examples in (16), the OM is m-/n-;
the variation in form is due to assimilation and not to any feature of the
verb. Lack of obligatoriness
Agreement morphology is usually obligatory in languages that
have such morphology (Baker 2011, Corbett 2006). It has also been proposed in
the literature (Woolford 2010) that there can only be one instance of agreement
per clause[4]. With these proposals in
mind, let us consider the examples below: (17a) | Nchídzí | wá- ka- bón-á | mbísá:na |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST see-FV | boy |
| 'Nchidzi saw a boy'. |
(17b) | *Nchídzí | ka - bón-á | mbísá:na |
| Nchidzi1a | PST- see-FV | boy |
| 'Nchidzi saw a boy'. |
(18) | a. | John rides a bicycle. |
| b. | * John ride a bicycle. (Standard English) |
Subject agreement is obligatory in
Ikalanga.finite sentences as it is in other Bantu languages (see
Mchombo 2004, 2001, Deen 2006, Letsholo 2004, 2007, Bresnan & Mchombo 1987,
Riedel 2009, Seidl & Dimitriadis 1997). Therefore leaving it out of a
sentence results in an ungrammatical sentence as attested in the Ikalanga
example (17b) and the English example (18b). Notice however, that the OM is not
obligatory in Ikalanga sentences: A sentence with a lexical object NP is
grammatical without the OM. Consider the examples in (19). (19a) | Nchídzí | wá- ka- -bón-á | mbísá:na. |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST- see-FV | boy |
| 'Nchidzi saw a boy'. |
(19b) | Nchídzí | wá- ka- m- bó:n-a, | mbísána. |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST- OM-see-FV | boy |
| 'Nchidzi saw him, the boy'. |
(19c) | Nchídzí | wá - ka- m- bó:n-a. |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST-OM-see-FV |
| 'Nchidzi saw him/her'. ( i.e. a specific boy) |
(19a) without the OM is grammatical while in (19b) the OM is
in anaphoric agreement with the NP mbisana
'boy'.Thus, OM lacks the obligatoriness that is associated
with agreement morphology. This fact has also been observed for languages like
Chichewa, Swahili and Amharic (Bresnan & Mchombo 1987, Deen 2006, and Kramer
respectively). One of the arguments posited in favor of the analysis of OMs as
agreement in Amharic by Baker (2010) is that there are instances where the OM,
just like agreement, is obligatory. One such instance involves experiencer
arguments of non-agentive verbs such as 'worry', astonish', ' hurt e.t.c. While
these kinds of verbs might trigger obligatory OMs in Amharic, this is not the
case in Ikalanga. In fact, including the OM in these constructions results in
ungrammaticality as observed in (20b and 21b) below. (20a) | Néó | wá-ka- | tshwények-a. |
| Neo1a | SA1-STAT. | worried-FV |
| 'Neo is worried'. |
(20b) | *Néó | wá-ka-n-tshwények-a. |
| Neo1a | SA1-STAT-OM1 - worried-FV |
| 'Neo is worried' |
(21a) | Néó | wá-ka-gwádzík-a. |
| Neo1a | SA1-STAT. hurt-FV |
| 'Neo is hurt' |
(21b) | *Néó | wá-ka-n-gwádzík-a. |
| Neo1a | SA1-STAT.-OM hurt-FV |
| 'Neo is hurt' |
Clearly this data cannot be used in any way to argue for
obligatoriness of OMs in Ikalanga and so I safely conclude that in Ikalanga the
OM is not obligatory except in instances where the lexical NP with which it
co-refers has been omitted as in (19c). 5.2 Syntactic
evidenceAgreement and
localityAgreement as understood in this paper, is a process in which
two elements which are in a local configuration share morphological feature
checking through a process of feature matching (Chomsky 1995, 2000). Consider
the data below: (22) | Mbísáná | íwó:yú, | badálá | bá-ká-búdzá | shé | kuti |
| boy | this | old men2 | SA2-PST-tell | chief | that |
| a-bá-ngák-e | bá-ká-n-khó:na |
| Neg.-SA1-can-SBJV | SA1-PST-OM1-manage |
| 'This boy, the elders told the chief that they cannot control
him'. |
Notice that the OM is in the lowermost embedded clause while
the NP with which it is co-referential, namely mbisana iwoyu 'this boy'
is in the highest clause. The SA, an agreement marker, is in a local relation
(Spec-head) with the NP (badala 'old men') with which it agrees. This
suggests that agreement morphology and the OM in Ikalanga behave differently in
terms of locality conditions, a fact which we can only account for if we
acknowledge that the OM is anaphoric and therefore is not bound by the same
locality conditions as agreement. It is indeed conceivable that there is a null
object pro in the lower clause which would then be in a local relation
with the OM similar to the subject pro in the same clause. While this is
a plausible analysis, the evidence against the agreement analysis is
nevertheless still compelling. Backward
pronominalizationKramer observes that although backward pronominalization
between subjects and objects in Amharic is almost ungrammatical, pronominalizing
the object improves the grammaticality of a sentence in Amharic. The fact that
such a sentence is grammatical means that the subject binds the OM. If the OM
can be bound by the subject, this means that it is a pronominal and not an
agreement marker since only arguments can be bound. The facts described for
Amharic hold true in Ikalanga. Consider the data below: (23a) | Néó | wá-ka-bó:na | nlúmé | ú:we |
| Neo1a | SA1-PST-see | husband | hers |
| ‘Neoi saw heri husband.’ |
(23b) | *Nlúmé | ú:we | wá-ka-bó:na | Néó |
| husband | hers | SA1-PST-see | Neo1a |
| ‘Heri husband saw Neoi’ |
(23c) | Nlúmé | ú:we | wá-ka-m-bó:na |
| husband | hers | SA1-PST-OM1-see |
| ‘Heri husband saw heri’ |
In example (23a), the subject binds the object NP and there
is no problem there. In (23b) however, the subject NP cannot bind the NP
Néó since this is an R-expression and it has to be free
everywhere. We can however explain the grammaticality of (23c) if we assume
that the OM m- is a pronominal and as such can be bound by the
R-expression nlume uwe 'her husband'. The status of the lexical NP in
sentences with OMIt has also been argued in the literature that an object
marker that functions as agreement morphology co-occurs with the NP it refers to
in the same phrase but that if the OM is a pronominal clitic then the NP with
which it co-refers is dislocated (see Bresnan & Mchombo, 1987). I provide
evidence in the sub-section below that the NP with which the OM co-refers in
Ikalanga is dislocated and that therefore the Ikalanga OM is a pronominal clitic
and not agreement morphology. The evidence I provide in favor of the claim that
the OM in Ikalanga is a pronominal clitic involves: a) the tonal patterns of the
verb, b) word order facts in transitives, ditransitives and adverb placement
and, c) lack of co-occurrence of OMs and question phrases. ToneMathangwane (1999: 189) observes that Ikalanga does not have
distinctive vowel lengthening but that nonetheless the language has a
penultimate vowel lengthening rule which applies at the right edge of a phrase.
A similar phenomena is observed for Chichewa by Bresnan & Mchombo
(henceforth B&M) (1987: 749) who note that in phrase-final position, tonal
changes are correlated with lengthening of the penultimate syllable. B&M go
on to propose that if the object marker and the lexical object NP are present in
Chichewa then the object NP is not an argument of the verb but an adjunct. One
piece of evidence they give in support of this idea is the effect of the
presence of the lexical NP on the tone of the verb. According to these authors,
the tone on the final vowel e of the subjunctive verb is low if the verb
is the final element of the verb phrase as in Chichewa ex. (24) in which the
subject NP ana anga 'my children' is postposed. Notice that in the
Ikalanga example (25), the subjunctive verb is in phrase final position, and
there is lengthening of the pen-ultimate syllable of the subjunctive verb
bike 'cook'. In addition, the tone on the final vowel of
this verb is low, just as in the Chichewa example. (24) | Ndikufúná | kutí | [a-pitirǐ:z-e] | aná | ánga. |
| I-want | that | SM-continue-SBJV | children | mine |
| 'I want my children to continue with the lesson'. (B&M 1987: ex:
19) |
(25) | Nd-ó-sháká | kúti | á- bí:k-e, | Neo |
| SA1-PRS want | that | SA1-cook-SBJV | Neo1a |
| 'I want her to cook, Neo'. |
If however, a non-postposed object NP follows the
subjunctive verb, two things happen: the low tone on the final vowel of the verb
changes to a high tone and there is lengthening of the penultimate syllable of
the item that is on the right-most edge of the verb phrase (ex. (26). These same
changes are observed in Ikalanga example (27). In this example, the lexical NP
nyama 'meat' is not postposed and the final vowel of the verb
bike 'cook' is high while the penultimate vowel of the syllable nyama
'meat' is lengthened. (26) | Ndi-kufúná | kutí | aná | ánga | [a-pitiriz-é | phúnzi:ro |
| I-want | that | children | my | SM-continue-SBJV | lesson |
| 'I want my children to continue with the lesson'. (B&M 1987: ex:
17) |
(27) | Ndó-sháká | kúti | Néo | a-bík-é | nyá:ma |
| SA1-pres want | that | Neo1a | SA1 cook-SBJV | meat9 |
| 'I want Neo to cook meat'. |
If on the other hand both the object marker and the lexical
object NP co-occur in a sentence, then the final vowel of the subjunctive verb
is low, suggesting that the verb is at the right edge of the VP and that the
lexical object NP is outside the VP. In Ikalanga example (28) the vowel
lengthening falls on the penultimate syllable of the verb, bi:, and the
tone on the final vowel of the subjunctive verb is low, marking the edge of the
VP. The object marker i- co-occurs with the lexical object NP
nyama 'meat'. Based on this (and other facts) B&M conclude that the
lexical NP in sentences in which the object marker co-occurs with the lexical
object NP is an adjunct rather than an argument of the verb since it occurs
outside of the verb phrase boundary. The Ikalanga data discussed so far are
consistent with B&M's conclusions, in other words, the verb phrase boundary
in say, example (28) is indicated by the vowel lengthening of the verb
bí:k-e as well as the low tone on the final
vowel of this verb since this is a declarative. This means that anything
that occurs beyond the verb phrase boundary is dislocated material. (28) | Nd- ó-sháká | kúti | Néo | á-í- bí:k-e, | nyama. |
| SA1-PRS -want | that | Neo1a | SA1 OM-cook-SBJV | meat9 |
| 'I want Neo to cook it, the meat'. |
Word orderIn this sub-section, I discuss word order facts relating to
adverb placement as well as word order in transitive and ditransitive sentences
in the quest to provide evidence that NPs that co-occur with OMs are dislocated
in Ikalanga. First, the adverb test. The adverb test
Consider the data below: (29a) | Néó | wá- ka- bík-á | nyama | madé:kwe. |
| Neo1a | SA1-PST- cook-FV | meat9 | yesterday |
| 'Neo cooked the meat yesterday'. |
(29b) | *Néó | wá- ka- bík-á | madékwe | nyama |
| Neo1a | SA1-PST- cook-FV | yesterday | meat9 |
| 'Neo cooked the meat yesterday'. |
(29c) | Néó | wá- ka- í-bík-á | madé:kwe, | nyama |
| Neo1a | SA1 –PST-OM-cook-FV | yesterday | meat9 |
| 'Neo cooked it yesterday, the meat'. |
In (29a), the edge of the VP is marked by the temporal
adverb madekwe and thus we assume that the object NP nyama 'meat'
forms part of VP. (29b) is ungrammatical because the object NP is outside the
domain of VP and therefore the theme theta role of the verb bika
'cook' has not been assigned. (29c) with the object marker is grammatical
providing further evidence for the argument proposed in B&M that when the
object marker is present, the lexical NP is an adjunct of the verb. In fact,
(29c) provides evidence that the object NP is outside VP since the vowel
lengthening falls on the penultimate syllable of the adverb madekwe
'yesterday' which marks the edge of VP. (29c) attests to the point made in
Riedel (2009) that in terms of word order, right dislocated elements follow
temporal adverbials cross linguistically. Thus the adverb test above provides
evidence that if the OM is present, then the lexical NP is not in the same
phrase (VP) as the OM in this language. This corroborates the point made above
that dislocated lexical NPs do not occur in the same phrase as the OMs with
which they co-refer if the OM is pronominal. Word order in
transitivesLanguages that display flexibility in word order have been
referred to in the literature as discourse configurational (Kiss 1995, Mchombo
2006). It is also assumed that these kinds of languages display flexibility
because they use topic and focus strategies which result in placement of NPs in
different positions. Ikalanga, at least to some degree, can be argued to be
discourse configurational as it allows flexibility of word order in sentences
that have an OM. Consider the examples below: (30a) | Néó | wá-ka-bíká | nyá:ma |
| Neo1a | SA-PST-cook | meat9 |
| 'Neo cooked meat'. (SVO) |
(30b) | Néó | wá-ka-í-bí:ka | nyáma. |
| Neo1a | SA1-PST-OM9-cook | meat9 |
| 'Neo cooked it, the meat'. (SVO) |
(30c) | Nyáma, | Néó | wá-ka-*(í)-bí:ka. |
| Meat9 | Neo1a | SA1-PST-OM9-cook |
| 'The meat, Neo cooked it'. (OVS) |
(30d) | Néó | nyáma | wá-ka-*(í)-bí:ka |
| Neo1a | meat | SA1-PST-OM-cook |
| 'Neo, the meat, she cooked it'. (OSV) |
(30e) | wá-ka-*(í)-bí:ka | Néó | nyáma |
| SA1-PST-OM9-cook | Neo1a | meat9 |
| 'She cooked it, Neo, the meat'. (VSO) |
Without the OM, examples (30c-30e) are ungrammatical. This
suggests that the lexical object NPs are topics in these sentences and that the
theme theta role has not been assigned if the OM is left out in these examples
hence the derivation crashes. In terms of the analysis proposed above, we can
explain the ungrammaticality of (30c – 30e) by saying that the EPP feature
of v has not been checked since the big DP containing the OM DP/D is not
there to check this feature. Word order in
ditransitivesThe canonical word order in ditransitive sentences in
Ikalanga is such that the indirect (applied) object precedes the direct object.
This is illustrated in (31a). (31a) | Nchídzí | wá-ka túmíl-íl-á | Ludó | líkwá:lo. |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST-send-APPL.-FV | Ludo1a | letter11 |
| 'Nchidzi sent Ludo a letter'. |
(31b) | *Nchídzí | wá-ka | túmíl-íl-á | líkwáló | Lu:do |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST- | send-appl.-FV | letter11 | Ludo1a |
| 'Nchidzi sent Ludo a letter'. |
(31c) | *Nchídzí | wá-ka | n-túmíl-íl-á | líkwáló, | Lu:do |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST-OM1- | send-appl.-FV | letter11 | Ludo1a |
| 'Nchidzi sent him/her a letter, Ludo'. |
(31d) | Nchídzi | wá-ka- | gú-túmíl-íl-á | Lu:do, | líkwá:ló |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST | OM11- send-APPL.-FV | Ludo1a | letter11 |
| 'Nchidzi sent it to Ludo, the letter'. |
(31e) | ?Nchídzí | wá-ka- | gú-n-túmíl-íl-á, | Lu:do, | líkwá:ló |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST | OM11- OM1- send-APPL.-FV | Ludo1a | letter11 |
| 'Nchidzi sent it to her, Ludo, the letter'. |
(31f) | Nchídzí | wá-ka- | gú-túmíl-íl-á | líkwá:ló | Lu:do |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST | OM11- send-APPL.-FV | letter11 | Ludo1a |
| 'Nchidzi sent it to Ludo, the letter'. |
(31g) | *Nchídzí | wá-ka- -n-túmíl-íl-á, | Lu:do, | líkwá:ló |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST-OM1- send-APPL.-FV | Ludo1a | letter11 |
| 'Nchidzi sent him/ her a letter', Ludo. |
Notice that (31b) in which the direct object precedes the
applied object, the sentence is ungrammatical. In (31c), the direct object comes
before the applied object because the lexical applied object NP Ludo
is not VP internal. Rather, what is VP internal is the OM. Notice the
lengthening of the penultimate vowel in the NP likwalo 'letter'
signalling a VP boundary. In essence, the applied object argument of the verb
namely the OM still precedes the direct object. (31d) is also grammatical with
the direct object displaced. (31e) is ungrammatical because it is unusual for
two OMs to occur on the same verb. The crucial examples from these data are
(31f) and (31g). The ungrammaticality of these two sentences attests to two
facts: a) the OM is not an agreement marker in Ikalanga: if it were, there would
be no reason why (31g) would be ungrammatical because the word order of the two
object NPs is what we expect to see in Ikalanga, namely applied object followed
by the direct object. b) the two lexical NPs in (31f & 31g) are VP external
and therefore there is a theta criterion violation since in each of the two
sentences there is a theta role that goes undischarged. Word order in embedded
sentencesIn (32a), the lexical NP mbisana iwoyu 'this boy' is
right dislocated while in (32b) both the subject NP badala 'old men' and
the lexical object NP are left dislocated. (32a) | Badálá | bá-ká-búdz-á | shé | kuti | a-bá-ngák-e |
| old men2 | SA2-PST-tell-FV | chief | that | Neg.-SA1-can-SBJV |
| bá-ká-n-khó:na, | mbísáná | íwóyú |
| SA1-PST-OM1-manage | boy1 | this |
| 'The elders told the chief that they cannot control him, this
boy'. |
(32b) | mbísáná | íwó:yú, | badálá | bá-ká-búdz-á | shé | kuti |
| boy | this | old men2 | SA2-PST-tell-FV | chief | that |
| a-bá-ngák-e | bá-ká-n-khó:na. |
| NEG-SA1-can-SBJV | SA1-PST OM1-manage |
| 'This boy, the elders told the chief that they cannot control
him'. |
In (32a), there is an intonation break before the extraposed
NP mbísáná íwóyú 'this boy',
signalling the edge of VP. In addition, consonant with the arguments raised in
section 5.2., there is vowel lengthening of the pen-ultimate syllable of the
verb khona 'the one'and this marks the VP boundary in this
sentence. Similarly, in (32b) there is an intonation break after the topicalized
NP mbísáná íwóyú 'this boy' and
there is lengthening of the pen-ultimate vowel of the verb khona 'the
one' which marks a phrase boundary. If these lexical NPs are not in the
same phrase as the OM, that suggests that the OM is a pronominal and not an
agreement marker. Question
constructionsIkalanga has two strategies for constructing WH questions
(see Letsholo, 2007 for a detailed discussion of WH constructions in
Ikalanga): a) in-situ (33a) | Ludó | wá-ka-téng-él-á | ání | bú:ka? |
| Ludo1a | SA1-PST-buy-APPL-FV | who | book |
| 'Who did Ludo buy a book?' (SA + V+ APPL+ Obj+ DO) |
b) Clefts (33b) | Ndí-ání | Lúdó | wa-á-ká- téng-él-á | bú:ka? |
| it is-who | Ludo1a | WHagr-SA-PST-buy-Appl-FV | book9 |
| 'Who did Ludo buy a book?' |
(34a) | Ludó | wá-ka-í-téng-él-á | á:ní, | bú:ka? |
| Ludo1a | SA1-PST-OM9- buy-APPL-FV | who | book |
| 'Who did Ludo buy it for, the book?' (Subj + V+ Appl +who+
DO) |
(34b) | *Ludó | wá-ka-n-téng-él-á | á:ní | bú:ka? |
| Ludo1a | SA1-PST-OM1- buy-APPL-FV | who | book |
| 'Who did Ludo buy the book for?' |
(34c) | *Ludó | wá-ka-í-téng-él-á | búka | á:ní? |
| Ludo1a | SA1-PST-OM9- buy-APPL-FV | book | who |
| 'Who did Ludo buy it for, the book?' |
(34d) | *Ludó | wá-ka-n-téng-él-á | búka | á:ní? |
| Ludo1a | SA1-PST-OM1- buy-APPL-FV | book | who |
| 'Who did Ludo buy a book?' |
(34e) | *Ndí-ání | Lúdó | wa-á-ká-n- téng-él-á | bú:ka? |
| it is-who | Ludo1a | WHagr-SA1-PST-OM21-buy-Appl-FV | book9 |
| 'Who did Ludo buy a book?' |
Example (34a) is grammatical: the OM is co-referential with
the dislocated direct object NP buka' and not with the WH phrase
ani 'who'. Notice the vowel lengthening on the penultimate vowel of the
WH word ani 'who', indicating a phrase boundary. Example
(34b) in which the WH phrase ani 'who' is co-referential with the
OM is ungrammatical. There is more than one explanation why this sentence is
ungrammatical. The first one is semantic and I leave it for discussion under
section 5.3; the other is syntactic and has to do with theta role assignment.
If, as already pointed out above, a DP which co-occurs with an OM is dislocated,
then anything that linearly follows this displaced DP is itself displaced. Thus,
if the DP ani is displaced, then it follows that the DP buka is
also displaced. This means that the verb tengela is one argument short, a
violation of the theta criterion. B&M (1987)’s lexical functional
grammar account for this kind of data is that WH phrases are focused
constituents and therefore they cannot be topics at the same time (see Demuth
& Johnson 1990 for similar observations regarding Setawana). The explanation above can be extended to example (34c), that is, this
sentence is ungrammatical because the OM is co-referential with the NP
buka 'book', which means that this NP is a topic and therefore
outside VP. If this NP is outside VP, then consequently anything else that comes
after it must be VP external, thus the WH word is also VP external. This means
there is a theta criterion violation in this sentence because the applicative
morpheme licences an extra theta role to the ones that the verb tenga
'buy' already has. If the NPs buka 'book' and ani 'who' are VP
external, this means one theta role has not been assigned hence the
ungrammaticality of this sentence. (34d) is a crucial example in this data in
that its ungrammaticality provides solid evidence that a DP which co-occurs with
an OM is dislocated in this language. In this example, both internal theta roles
have been assigned: the goal theta role to the big DP containing the OM, and the
theme theta role to buka. Why then is this sentence still
ungrammatical? The ungrammaticality of this sentence can be explained if the WH
word is an adjunct in this sentence, meaning it does not get a chance to move to
the relevant specifier where it checks its question feature. (34e) is
ungrammatical because both the WH word and the OM receive the same theta role
(goal), a violation of the theta criterion. The evidence adduced so far
regarding the syntactic status of lexical object DPs that co-occur with OMs is
consistent with the properties of dislocated constituents outlined in Riedel
(2009:68) which are as follows: A right dislocated
phrase:
- is a nominal phrase in clause final (or initial)
position (following/preceding all of the core sentence
components,
- is co-indexed with a pronominal
element inside the clause
- has an afterthought
reading
- is phrased separately
phonologically
5.3 The semantic
characteristics of the OMIt is common knowledge in linguistics that agreement has no
semantic bearing on a sentence (Lasnik 1999, Rezac 2010): all it does is to
render a sentence as grammatical or ungrammatical without changing the meaning
of a sentence in any given way. This is not what the OM does in Ikalanga. In
this language (and other languages e.g. Chichewa and Amharic), the existence of
the OM induces a definiteness/specificity effect on a DP in addition to adding
emphasis. These facts can be explained if we assume that the big DP containing
the OM shifts from its base position to spec VP as per the analysis proposed in
this paper. Definiteness Like other Bantu languages, Ikalanga lacks determiners such
as those found in languages like English (a, an, the) which are used to indicate
definiteness (see Riedel 2009 for a similar observation regarding other Bantu
languages). Consider the example below: (35) | Néó | wá- ka- bón-á | mbísána. |
| Neo1a | SM1-PST- see-FV | boy1 |
| 'Neo saw a boy. |
| Mbísána | wá- | khóná | wá-ka- bé-á-ka-tathá | do:nkí. |
| Boy1 | SA1 | particular | SA1-PST PROG.-SA1-PST-ride | donkey |
| That particular boy was riding a donkey'. |
In the absence of determiners as mentioned above, like other
Bantu languages (Riedel 2009), demonstratives and possessives can function like
definite articles in Ikalanga. This is illustrated in (36). It is however
possible to use the OM in these sentences where demonstratives and possessives
have been used to function as definite articles. When this happens, the OM has
two effects on the semantics of the sentence a) the DP with which the OM
co-refers acquires definiteness and b) the DP becomes emphatic (37a&b). The
definite effect induced on DPs by OMs is also observed in other Bantu languages
such as Zulu (Wald, 1979) and Kihung'an (Takizala, 1973) both cited in Morimoto
(2002). (36a) | Nchídzí | wá-ka-téngá | lórí | íyé:yi. |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST-buy | car9 | this |
| 'Nchidzi bought this car'. |
(36b) | Néó | wá- ka-tátá | ng'wáná | wá:bo. |
| Neo1a | SA1-PST-throw out | child1 | their |
| 'Neo threw out their child'. |
(37a) | Nchídzí | wá-ka-i-té:ngá | lórí | íyeyi |
| Nchidzi1a | SA1-PST-OM9-buy | car9 | this |
| 'Nchidzi did buy it, this car'. |
(37b) | Néó | wá- ka-n-tá:ta | ng'wáná | wábo. |
| Neo1a | SA1-PST-OM1- throw out | child1 | theirs |
| 'Neo did throw him/her out, their child'. |
If it is indeed the case that agreement has no semantic
effect on a sentence, the fact that the OM has a definiteness effect as well as
an emphatic bearing on the NP it co-refers with cannot be accounted for if we
analyze OM as agreement. Further evidence that OMs are not agreement morphology in Ikalanga comes
from WH constructions. As already shown in section 5.2. WH phrases cannot
co-refer with OMs. This is partly because WH phrases are indefinite DPS and
following the discussion above about the association of OMs and definiteness and
specificity, it is to be expected that the OM cannot co-occur with WH words in
the same clause in this language. This prediction is borne out as example (34b)
repeated as (38) below illustrates. (38) | *Ludó | wá-ka-n-téng-él-á | áni | bú:ka? |
| Ludo1a | SA1-PST-OM1 -buy-APPL-FV | who | book |
| 'Who did Ludo buy a book for?' (SA + V+ APPL+ Obj+ DO) |
OM and
specificityIn terms of specificity, OM does play a role in
distinguishing between specific and non-specific objects in Ikalanga. Riedel
(2009) observes the same for Mainland Swahili while Kramer observes the same for
Amharic. OM marked objects are always specific in Ikalanga. This fact is
consonant with observations made in the literature, for example,
Thráinsson (2001) who concludes that shifted objects must be interpreted
specifically. In the analysis proposed in this paper, the DP containing the OM
raises to Spec vP where presumably its specificity feature is also
checked. (39a) | Néó | wá- ka- bón-á | mbísána. |
| Neo1a | SA1-PST-see-FV | boy1 |
| 'Neo saw a boy'. |
(39b) | Néó | wá- ka-m bó:n-a | mbísána. |
| Neo1a | SA1 -PST-OM- see-FV | boy1 |
| 'Neo saw him, the boy'. |
Thus the morpheme m- brings about a meaning
difference between (39a) and (39b). According to informants that I interviewed
in Botswana, the NP mbisana 'boy' in (39a) has a non-specific meaning; it
does not refer to any specific boy. On the other hand, the morpheme m- in
(39b) brings about specificity. Further evidence that OM brings specificity to
an NP comes from the fact that non-specific objects cannot be object-marked.
Consider the data below: (40a) | A-kúná | cha-ndá-ka-bó:na. |
| NEG-nothing | NEGagr-SA1-PST-see |
| 'I did not see anything'. |
(40b) | *A-kúná | cha-ndá-ka-chi-bó:na. |
| NEG-nothing | NEGagr-SA1-PST-OM7 see |
| 'I did not see anything'. |
(41a) | A-kúná | wa-bá-ka-sí:ya. |
| NEG.-nothing | Agr1-SA1-PST-leave |
| 'They did not leave anyone behind' |
(41b) | *A-kúná | wa-bá-ka-n-sí:ya. |
| NEG.-nothing | Agr1-SA1-PST-OM1- leave |
| 'They did not leave anyone behind' |
The (b) examples in (40 – 41) are ungrammatical
because the non-specific DP akuna 'nothing' co-refers with the OMs in
these sentences. 6. ConclusionThis paper makes contributions to the debate on the status
of object markers in general but specifically in Bantu languages. The paper
investigates the status of OMs in Ikalanga from both perspectives: that is, as
agreement morphology and as pronominal clitics. In favor of the agreement
analysis, the paper has argued that OMs attach only to the verbal stem and not
to any other lexical category such as nouns or auxiliaries as do clitics in
Indo-European languages. This behavior is consistent with agreement morphology.
In addition, the paper has pointed out that in Ikalanga only one OM occurs per
clause although there are instances where native speakers have judged some
sentences with two OMs in a clause as possible in the language. Further, the
paper has pointed out that OMs share grammatical features (person, gender and
number) with the lexical NP with which they co-refer just like agreement
morphology would. The paper also presented arguments in favor of the pronominal analysis.
Using morphosyntactic evidence, the paper argued that OMs in Ikalanga are not
agreement markers but pronominal clitics similar to Italian/Romance clitics
(Cardinaletti 2007). For example, the paper has shown that subject markers,
which are agreement morphology, change form in response to changes in modality
and negation while OMs, which are pronominal clitics maintain the same
morphological form irrespective of changes in these syntactic phenomena. In
addition, the paper also argued that agreement morphology is obligatory in order
for a sentence to be rendered grammatical, e.g. subject markers in Ikalanga but
OMs are not obligatory in this language. Further, the paper showed that
agreement, for example between a subject and subject marker is a relation that
is bound by locality conditions in this language, specifically spec-head
relation. However, the locality condition of spec-head relation is not required
for OMs since they can occur several clauses away from their
antecedents. In addition, the paper also argued that when a lexical object DP
co-occurs with the OM, then it (the lexical object DP) is not an argument of the
verb; rather, it is an adjunct. This has been used in the literature as evidence
that the OM in such cases is a pronominal and not agreement. Evidence that the
lexical DPs which co-refer with OMs in Ikalanga are adjuncts comes from
phonological facts to do with vowel lengthening and tonal patterns which mark
phrase boundaries in the language. More evidence for the adjuncthood of these
lexical DPs comes from word order facts, and WH constructions. Furthermore, the
paper showed that the occurrence of OMs in Ikalanga has a semantic import in the
language, something that agreement morphology does not do. For example, OMs have
a definiteness and specificity effect on lexical DPs with which they co-occur.
When OMs co-occur with definite DPs such as those with demonstratives or
possessives, their effect is to emphasize. Evidence that OMs are associated with
specificity comes from the fact that they cannot co-occur with non-specific NPs
such as ‘anything’ or ‘no one’ or WH phrases. ReferencesBaker, Mark. 2011. On the relationship of object agreement and
accusative case: Evidence from Amharic. Linguistic Inquiry (available from
website: http://www.rci.rutgers.edu/~mabaker/Amharic-AgrO-Case-revised.pdf) Bresnan, Joan. & Sam Mchombo. 1987. ‘Topic, pronoun and
agreement in Chichewa’. Language 63. 741 – 782. doi:10.2307/415717 Cardinalleti, Anna. 2007. On different types of clitic clusters.
University of Venice Working Papers in Linguistics 17. 27 -
76. Chomsky, Noam. 2001. ‘Derivation by phase’. Ken Hale: A
Life in Language, ed. by Michael Kenstowicz, 1- 52. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press. -----. 2000. Minimalist inquiries: The Framework. Step by Step:
Essays on Minimalist Syntax in Honor of Howard Lasnik, ed. by Roger Martin,
David Michaels & Uriagereka. 89 – 155. Cambridge: MIT
Press. -----. 1995. The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, Mass.: The
MIT Press. Corbett, Greville. 2006. Agreement. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. Deen, Kamil. 2006. Subject agreement in Nairobi Swahili. Selected
Proccedings of the 35th Annual Conference on African Linguistics. ed.
by John Mugane, 225 – 233.Cascadilla Proceedings Project.
Demuth, Katherine. & Mark Johnson. 1989. Interaction between
discourse functions and agreement in Setawana. Journal of African Languages and
Linguistics 11. 22 – 35. doi:10.1515/jall.1989.11.1.21 Hyman, Larry, M. & Duranti Allesandro. 1982. On the object
relations in Bantu. Syntax and Semantics 15. 217 – 239. Jelinek, Eloise. (1984). Empty categories, case and
configurationality. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 2, 39
-76. doi:10.1007/bf00233713 Keach, Camilla, N. 1995. Subject and object markers as agreement
and pronoun incorporation in Swahili. Theoretical Approaches to African
Linguistics ed. by Akinbiyi Akinlabi, 109 - 116. Trenton, New Jersey: Africa
World Press. Kiss, Katalina. 1995. Discourse Configurational Languages. New
York: Oxford University Press. Kramer, Ruth. Under review. Clitic doubling or object agreement: an
Amharic investigation, available at http://www9.georgetown.edu/faculty/rtk8/Clitic%20Doubling%20or%20Object%20Agreement.pdf. Labelle, Marie. 2007. Pronominal object markers in Bantu and
Romance. The Bantu – Romance connection. A comparative investigation of
verbal agreement DPs and information structure ed. by Cecile de Cat &
Katherine Demuth. Linguistiks Actuell/Linguistics Today, 83–109 John
Benjamins. doi:10.1075/la.131.07lab Lasnik, Howard. 1999. Minimalist Analysis. Oxford:
Blackwell. Letsholo, Rose. 2004. Clausal and DP internal agreement in
Ikalanga. Studies in African Linguistics 33/1. 91 - 127. -----. 2007. Who is where: Deriving right edge WH phrases in
Ikalanga WH constructions. Lingua 117. 986 – 1007. doi:10.1016/j.lingua.2006.05.005 Marten, Lutz. & Nancy Kula (ms.). Object marking and
morphosyntactic variation in Bantu. Mathangwane, Joyce. T. 1999. Ikalanga Phonetics and Phonology: A
Synchronic and Diachronic Study. CSLI Publications: Stanford CA. Matushansky, Ora. 2006. Head movement in linguistic theory.
Linguistic Inquiry 37. 69 - 109. doi:10.1162/002438906775321184 Mchombo, Sam. 2001. Efects of Headmarking on constituent order in
Chichewa. Proceedings of the LFG Conference, ed. by Miriam Butt & Tracy
Holloway King, CSLI Online Publications, http://cslpublications.stanford.edu/LFG -----. 2002. Affixes, clitics and Bantu morphosyntax. Language
Universals and Variation, ed. by Mengistu Amberber & Peter Collins, 185-210.
Westport CT: Prager. -----. 2004. The Syntax of Chichewa. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press. -----. 2006. Linear ordering constraints on split NPs in Chichewa.
ZAS Papers in Linguistics 43. 143 - 160. Morimoto, Yokiko. 2002. Prominence mismatches and differential
object marking in Bantu. Proceedings of the LFG02 Conference. 292 –
314. CLSI Publications. Mullen, Dana. 1986. Issues in the morphology and phonology of
Amharic: the lexical generation of pronominal clitics. Doctoral dissertation,
University of Ottawa. Nash, Jay. 1992. Aspects of Ruwund grammar. PhD dissertation,
University of Illinois at Urbana - Champaign. Rezac, Milan. 2010. φ Agree
versus φ feature movement: evidence from floating quatifiers.
Linguistic Inquiry 41. 496 -508. doi:10.1162/ling_a_00007 Riedel, Kristina. 2009. The Syntax of Object Marking in Sambaa: A
Comparative Bantu Perspective. LOT: The Netherlands. Seidl, Amanda. & Alexis. Dimitriadis. 1997. The discourse
function of object marking in Swahili. CLS 33: The Main Session
(1997). 373 – 389. Chicago Linguistics Society. Takizala, Alexis. 1973. Focus and relativization: The case of
Kihung'an. Syntax and Semantics 2. ed. by John P. Kimball, 123- 148. New York:
New York Academic Press. Thráinsson, Hȫskuldur. 2001. Object shift and
scrambling. The Handbook of Syntactic Theory.ed. by Mark Baltin and Chris
Collins, 148 - 202. Malden, M.A: Blackwell. Torrego, Esther. 1995. On the nature of clitic doubling. Evolution
and revolution in Linguistic Theory, ed. by Hector Campos, 399-418. Washington
DC: Georgetown Press. Wald, Benji. 1979. ‘The development of the Swahili object
marker: A study of the interaction of syntax and discourse’. Discourse and
Syntax Vol.12 of Syntax and Semantics, ed.by Talmy
Givón, 505-524. New York: Academic
Press. Woolford, Ellen. 2010. Active-stative agreement in Lakota. Ms.
UMass Amherst. available at http://people.umass.edu/ellenw/
Contact information:
Rose Letsholo
Department of English
University of Botswana
Private Bag 00703
Gaborone, Botswana
Fax: (267) 318-5098
Tel: (267) 355-4124
letsholor@mopipi.ub.bw
[1]Abbreviations: APPL. =
applicative, COND. = conditional, FUT. = future tense, FV = final vowel, NEG. =
negation, OM = object marker, PRS = present tense, PST = past tense, SA/SM =
subject agreement marker, SBJV = subjunctive, STAT = stative, VR = verb
root [2]Notice that the vowel
in the verb 'bona' in (4a) is short while the same vowel in (4b&c) is long.
The reasons for this distinction will be discussed in section
5.2.3.1. [3]The only Kramer article
referenced in this paper is the one under review and henceforth I reference it
just as ‘Kramer’ in the text. [4]Notice though that if
this proposal is correct, in all languages that have subject agreement, all OMs
will have to be analyzed as pronominals regardless of the characteristics that
they display. |