Volume 8 Issue 1 (2010)
DOI:10.1349/PS1.1537-0852.A.368
Note: Linguistic Discovery uses Unicode characters
to represent phonetic symbols. Please see Optimizing Display
for requirements to accurately reproduce this page.
Can semantic maps be built purely bottom-up?
Comment on ‘Building a semantic map: top-down versus
bottom-up approaches’ by Ferdinand de Haan (2010)
Joost Zwarts
Utrecht Institute of Linguistics OTS
Methodological considerations of semantic mapping play an
important role in the papers of this issue. De Haan (2010) argues for a
bottom-up approach in building semantic maps. In his view, domains (like
“modality” versus “evidentiality”) cannot and should not
be distinguished until a map has been constructed that is based on a study of
the meanings of individual morphemes. That might be a useful way to avoid
semantic discussions about ‘where’ an item belongs, but some
critical notes are in order about the way such a bottom-up approach might be
done without top-down
considerations[1]
In a bottom-up approach, the data underdetermine the map, as shown in
the case of Dutch
moeten. The three meanings of
moeten allow four
possible maps. De Haan chooses one possible map, without further argumentation,
but the question arises on what basis the lines are drawn in such a situation,
if we do not want to use
top-down semantic information about the
similarity between meanings and the domains they belong to. A purely bottom-up
procedure is not possible then.
De Haan identifies and classifies meanings of modal items in a rough
descriptive way (“evaluation of evidence”, “strong epistemic
modality”, “assertion of indirect evidence”,
“predictive”, “future”). It is not clear how we can
actually do this, without having some good idea about the broader semantic
domains from which these meanings are drawn. It would be more in line with a
real bottom-up approach to use neutral numbers for situations to which sentences
apply, without bothering about the semantic description of those situations.
However, that requires a rather different, “stimulus-driven”
approach, like that of Levinson and Meira (2003) or Majid et al. (2007), where
the points on the map are really theory-neutral to an important extent. This is
probably not what de Haan would want to do, since he is clearly interested (and
rightfully so) in how a set of more abstract modal/evidential meanings hangs
together.
Another potential problem with the bottom-up approach is its partiality.
In his paper, de Haan presents an essentially linear arrangement of meanings
ranging from purely epistemic to purely temporal, with evidential as a category
in the middle:[2]
|
strong — evaluative — assertive — predictive —
future
|
As he points out, some of the items discussed have other
meanings too (e.g. “obligation”), but these are left out of the
picture. In general, an analysis is always partial to a certain extent (in the
sense that we restrict ourselves to a particular set of meanings), but in
semantic maps this partiality carries a certain risk. We don’t know
whether “strong” and “future” are really far apart from
each other on the map or whether this is an accidental result of the way items
and meanings are selected. Including the “obligation” meaning,
together with some more items from different languages, might easily result in a
more connective map in which ‘strong’ and ‘future’ are
then more closely related and the domains of epistemic modality and future
interact with each other. What this shows is that we need some idea of the
constellation of meanings making up a domain (or family of domains) before (or
in addition to) building its semantic map, so that the partiality of our
representation results from a well-informed abstraction and not from a more
accidental lack of data.
As de Haan writes in footnote 18, a “merger” of top-down and
bottom-up methods has proved to be the best way to go in parsing (computational
linguistics). I hope that my comments on de Haan’s paper suggest that the
same is true for semantic maps (typological linguistics). It is not top-down
versus bottom-up, but rather top-down
and bottom-up.
References
de Haan, Ferdinand. 2010. Building a semantic map: top-down versus
bottom-up approaches. Linguistic Discovery, this issue. doi:10.1349/ps1.1537-0852.a.347
Levinson, Stephen C. and Sérgio Meira. 2003. 'Natural
concepts' in the spatial topological domain – Adpositional meanings in
crosslinguistic perspective: An exercise in semantic typology. Language
79/3.485-516. doi:10.1353/lan.2003.0174
Majid, Asifa, Melissa Bowerman, Miriam van Staden and James S.
Boster. 2007. The semantics of ‘cutting and breaking’ events: A
cross-linguistic perspective. Cognitive Linguistics
18/2.133-152.
Author’s contact information:
Joost Zwarts
Opleiding Taalwetenschap
Departement Moderne Talen
Faculteit Geesteswetenschappen
Universiteit Utrecht
Trans 10
3512 JK Utrecht
The Netherlands
j.zwarts@uu.nl
[1]
De Haan writes as if an
item (like English
must or Tuyuca
-yi) all by itself can be called
epistemic modal or evidential marker. But that cannot be correct in general. We
know that items can be polysemous and span different domains. If we classify
anything into domains, then it is individual meanings or functions. Lexical or
grammatical items can only belong to a domain in a derivative and somewhat
uninteresting sense.
[2]
I am taking the
“geometry” of the map seriously here, ignoring the way de Haan
‘warps’ this semantic map so that ‘future’ is below
‘evaluative’, though still unconnected to it. What counts, of
course, are the connections, not the way the map is displayed on a
two-dimensional piece of paper.
|