Volume 7 Issue 1 (2009)
DOI:10.1349/PS1.1537-0852.A.334
Note: Linguistic Discovery uses Unicode characters
to represent phonetic symbols. Please see Optimizing Display
for requirements to accurately reproduce this page.
Participles and Finiteness: The Case of Akhvakh
Denis Creissels
Université Lumière (Lyon 2)
Akhvakh, a Nakh-Daghestanian language belonging to the Andic
(sub-) branch of the Nakh-Daghestanian family, has participial relative clauses
headed by verb forms that can also head independent clauses. Akhvakh data
contradict the inflectional approach to finiteness according to which finiteness
as a clausal feature necessarily correlates with the morphological structure of
verb forms, and support a constructional approach to finiteness. In particular,
the formulation of a general definition of participles must be compatible with
the fact that forms found in relative clauses in which they behave at the same
time as verbal heads and as adjectival dependents of a head noun may also head
constructions having a different status with respect to finiteness.
1. Introduction
Akhvakh (
ašoƛ̱i
mic̱’i
, Russian
axvaxskij
jazyk
)
[1]
belongs to the Andic
(sub-)branch of the Northeast Caucasian (or Nakh-Daghestanian)
family.
[2]
Like the other Andic
languages, Akhvakh has no writing tradition. According to Magomedova &
Abdulaeva (2007), Akhvakh has approximately 20 000 speakers. Four dialects
are traditionally recognized. One of them is designated as Northern Akhvakh,
whereas the other three are grouped under the label of Southern Akhvakh.
Northern Akhvakh is spoken in four villages of the Axvaxskij Rajon in
the western part of Daghestan (Tadmagitl’, Lologonitl’,
Kudijab-Roso, and Izani), and in Axaxdərə near Zaqatala (Azerbaijan),
where I carried field work on
Akhvakh.
[3]
The Southern Akhvakh
dialects are spoken in one village each (Cegob, Tljanub and Ratlub), all
situated in the Šamil’skij Rajon of Daghestan.
The analysis proposed in this paper is entirely based on field work
carried in Axaxdərə between June 2005 and April 2008. Judging from the
data available on AR Akhvakh, there does not seem to be any contrast between AD
Akhvakh and the other varieties of Northern Akhvakh in the aspects of grammar
dealt with in this paper, but in the absence of more detailed information on AR
Akhvakh I prefer to leave this question open.
Traditionally, finiteness is viewed as a morphological characterization
of some verb forms correlating with their ability to combine with a canonical
subject NP and to head independent clauses, and participles are viewed as a
subtype of the more general type
non-finite verb form. The aim of this
paper is to show that Akhvakh data is incompatible with this position, and
provides evidence supporting the approach to finiteness according to which
finiteness is a feature of
predicative constructions not necessarily
correlated in a simple way with the morphological structure of the verb forms
involved.
The paper is organized as follows. In section 2, I review the main
theoretical approaches to finiteness, and I briefly comment Kalinina &
Sumbatova’s proposal to recognize a Nakh-Daghestanian type of finiteness.
In section 3, I give some basic information about Akhvakh morphosyntax. In
section 4, I examine several aspects of Akhvakh morphosyntax relevant to the
question of finiteness. Section 5 is devoted to participles. Section 6 puts the
particularities of Akhvakh participles described in section 5 in their
historical perspective.
2. Theoretical Approaches to
Finiteness
The notion of finiteness originates in the traditional
division found in Latin grammars between verbal forms inflected for person
(‘verba finita’) and verbal forms devoid of person inflection
(‘verba infinita’: infinitives, participles, gerunds, and
supines).
According to what can be called the inflectional approach to finiteness,
the
finite vs.
nonfinite distinction relies on the presence vs.
absence of some inflectional characteristics, not only person, as in traditional
Latin grammar, but also tense, and sometimes others too. The importance given to
the classification of verb forms according to the presence vs. absence of some
inflectional distinctions reflects the widespread view that “only finite
verbs are able to form an independent utterance and that each independent
utterance must have one and only one finite verb.” (Nikolaeva
2007a:3)
The limitations of this conception are well-known. The inflectional
features posited as being responsible for finiteness are not universal, and
counterexamples to the hypothesis of a universal correlation between reduced
inflection and inability to head independent clauses are easy to find –
see in particular (Nikolaeva 2007a), (Nikolaeva 2007b). This correlation is at
best a tendency calling for functional explanations – see (Cristofaro
2007), (Bisang 2007).
Generative syntax developed a more abstract notion of finiteness viewed
as a clausal category with the status of functional head, responsible for a
variety of syntactic phenomena, in particular the presence of an overt subject
in the nominative case in finite clauses, contrasting with its absence in
nonfinite structures (control and raising structures, structures in which the
subject of a dependent clause receives its Case from the main verb or from the
complementizer). Generative syntax also developed the idea that finiteness is
relevant to the distribution of referential expressions and anaphoric elements,
in the sense that dependent finite clauses constitute opaque domains, not
accessible to rules operating in the main clause, as opposed to the
accessibility (or transparency) of nonfinite clauses.
However, until recently, the generative approach to finiteness
maintained an essential element of the traditional approach, namely the
hypothesis of a universal correlation between the syntactic properties of verb
forms and the richness of specification of agreement and tense. Faced with data
contradicting this assumption, some authors have explored solutions that make it
possible to handle the individual cases without entirely dropping the basic
tenets of the inflectional approach, but others, in line with the functional
literature, have concluded that there is no universal correlation between
finiteness as a clausal category and verbal morphology, although there are
obvious cross-linguistic tendencies.
In the constructional approach to finiteness, developed in various
non-transformational frameworks (Sells 2007), finiteness is a formal
characterization of clauses accounting for their ability to constitute
independent utterances with particular illocutionary forces and/or the way they
can be inserted as constituents of complex structures, but there is no a priori
limitation on the possible manifestations of finiteness. Situations where
finiteness as a grammatical feature of clauses straightforwardly correlates with
the choice between different morphological types of verb forms are viewed as
only one of the possible ways of encoding finiteness, and the recognition of the
status of a clause with respect to finiteness may also rely on a particular
combination of words that, taken individually, cannot be analyzed as bearing
finiteness markers. Note also that, in this conception, finiteness must not
necessarily be conceived as a binary feature.
Before turning to the presentation and analysis of Akhvakh data, a
remark is in order about the hypothesis of a Nakh-Daghestanian type of
finiteness put forward by Kalinina & Sumbatova (2007). In spite of the fact
that one of the three languages they analyze (Bagvala) is a close relative of
Akhvakh, most of their generalizations are contradicted by the variety of
Akhvakh analyzed in this paper. Two grammatical points are particularly crucial
in their characterization of a Nakh-Daghestanian type of finiteness: the
existence of a particular class of auxiliaries, termed ‘predicative
particles’, that attach to the head of the focus phrase, and a tendency
towards overt morphosyntactic marking of focused constituents. None of the
examples they quote to illustrate these points can be transposed to AD Akhvakh.
In particular, in AD Akhvakh, the copula in auxiliary function consistently
follows the auxiliated verb, and therefore does not participate in focus
marking. Note that the existence of this kind of contrast between closely
related languages is not exceptional, since a similar contrast has been observed
for example between Basque dialects: as shown by Rebuschi (1984:71-77), in most
varieties of Basque, the auxiliary immediately follows the auxiliated verb, and
moves from this position only in negative clauses, but in the dialects of the
French Basque Country (Navarro-Labourdin), the auxiliary acts as a focus marker
much in the same way as in the Daghestanian languages analyzed by Kalinina &
Sumbatova.
3. General Remarks on Akhvakh
Morphosyntax
3.1 Clause
Structure
AD Akhvakh clause structure is characterized by flexible
constituent order, without clear evidence of a preferred position for focalized
constituents.
As illustrated by ex. (1), case marking and gender-number agreement
between the verb and its core arguments are consistently ergative. In contrast,
assertive agreement (see section 3.4.3) follows a split intransitive
pattern.
(1)
|
a.
|
waša
|
w-oq’-ari.
|
|
|
boy
|
M-come-PFV
[4]
|
|
|
‘The boy came.’
|
|
b.
|
aḵ’a
|
j-eq’-ari.
|
|
|
woman
|
F-come-PFV
|
|
|
‘The woman came.’
|
|
c.
|
imiχi
|
b-eq’-ari.
|
|
|
donkey
|
N-come-PFV
|
|
|
‘The donkey came.’
|
|
d.
|
aḵ’a-λ̱-e
|
imiχi
|
b-eƛ-ari.
|
|
|
woman-OF-ERG
|
donkey
|
N-bring-PFV
|
|
|
‘The woman brought the
donkey.’
|
|
e.
|
aḵ’a-λ̱-e
|
waša
|
w-oƛ-ari.
|
|
|
woman-OF-ERG
|
boy
|
M-bring-PFV
[5]
|
|
|
‘The woman brought the
boy.’
|
|
f.
|
milica-s̱w-e
|
aḵ’a
|
j-eƛ-ari.
|
|
|
policeman-OM-ERG
|
woman
|
F-bring-PFV
|
|
|
‘The policeman brought the
woman.’
|
Arguments whose identity is recoverable from the context can
freely be omitted, and unexpressed arguments receiving an arbitrary
interpretation are common too.
Causative is the only valency-changing mechanism systematically
expressed via verb morphology or grammaticalized periphrases.
3.2 Nouns and Noun
Phrases
Three semantically transparent agreement classes of nouns
are distinguished in the singular: human masculine (M), human feminine (F), and
non-human (N).
[6]
In the plural, the
distinction
masculine vs.
feminine is neutralized, resulting in a
binary opposition
human plural (HPL) vs.
non-human plural (NPL).
Noun morphology shows only frozen vestiges of gender prefixes.
In canonical NPs, the head noun is in final position and is inflected
for number and case. Noun dependents other than adjectives show no agreement
mark and the agreement morphology of attributive adjectives is reduced in
comparison with AR Akhvakh or the other Andic
languages.
[7]
As illustrated by ex. (2), in the absence of a head noun, the last word
of the NP, whatever its nature, is marked for gender, number and case.
(2)
|
a.
|
hu
|
ʕoloq̄ada
|
jašo-de
|
q̄’õhula
|
gw-ēri.
|
|
|
DEM
|
young
|
girlO-ERG
|
food
|
do-PFV
[8]
|
|
|
‘This young girl did the
cooking.’
|
|
b.
|
hu
|
ʕoloq̄ada-λ̱-e
|
q̄’õhula
|
gw-ēri.
|
|
|
DEM
|
young-OF-ERG
|
food
|
do-PFV
|
|
|
‘This young one did the
cooking.’
|
|
c.
|
hu-λ̱-e
|
q̄’õhula
|
gw-ēri.
|
|
|
DEM-OF-ERG
|
food
|
do-PFV
|
|
|
‘This one did the cooking.’,
‘She did the cooking.’
|
Number inflection of nouns is irregular and involves
considerable free variation.
Except for 1st and 2nd person singular pronouns, whose absolute form is
characterized by a non-void ending
-ne
,
the absolute form of nominals (used in the extra-syntactic function of quotation
or designation and in S or P roles) has no overt mark. Case suffixes may attach
to a stem identical with the absolute form, or to a special
oblique stem.
In the singular, the formation of the oblique stem is very irregular and
involves considerable free variation. The formation of the oblique stem is more
regular in the plural. In particular, ‘oblique stem markers’
expressing class distinctions (M
-s̱u-
, F/N
-
λ
̱i-
,
HPL
-lo-
, NPL
-le- ~ -li-
) are more systematically used
in the plural than in the singular. Ex. (3) illustrates the variety in the
possible relationships between the absolute forms and oblique stems of nouns, in
the singular and in the plural.
(3)
|
Plural marking and oblique stem formation in AD
Akhvakh
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
ABS.SG
|
OBL.SG
|
ABS.PL
|
OBL.PL
|
|
‘woman’
|
aḵ’a
|
aḵ’a-λ̱i-
|
aḵ’-o
|
aḵ’-o-lo-
|
|
‘girl’
|
jaše
|
jaš-o-
|
jaše-li
|
jaše-l(i-l)o-
|
|
‘shepherd’
|
išwa
|
išwa-s̱u-
|
išu-li
|
išu-l(i-l)o-
|
|
‘king’
|
χani
|
χã-s̱u
|
χã-di
|
χã-di-lo-
|
|
‘dog’
|
χwe
|
χwe-
|
χwa-di
|
χwa-di-le-
|
|
‘animal’
|
ħema
|
ħema-λ̱i-
|
ħema-na
|
ħema-n(a-l)e-
|
|
‘calf’
|
ƛe
|
ƛe-ro-
|
ƛe-ra
|
ƛe-ra-le-
|
|
‘bag’
|
q’ẽƛe
|
q’ẽƛe-no-
|
q’ẽƛe-na
|
q’ẽƛe-n(a-l)e-
|
|
‘flower’
|
c̱ic̱i
|
c̱ic̱i(-λ̱i)-
|
c̱ic̱-a
|
c̱ic̱-a-le-
|
Case inflection includes the following cases:
- ergative
(-de),
- dative
(-ƛa),
- genitive
(Ø or
-ƛ̱i),[9]
- comitative
(-k’ena),
- purposive
(-ʁana),
- five series of spatial cases, which however
tend to depart from the typical Daghestanian pattern in that one of the series
(the
-g-
series) is a default series that
does not encode a particular spatial configuration, and spatial configurations
tend to be encoded by combining NPs showing default spatial case marking with
locative adverbs showing parallel spatial case inflection, rather than via
‘traditional’ case marking.
Each series of spatial cases includes an essive
(-i
or
-e), a lative
(-a), and an elative
(-u(ne)),[10]
and the distinction between 3 spatial cases applies to locative adverbs too.
3.3. Adjectives
Like verbs (see section 3.4.2), adjectives divide into those
obligatorily including a class agreement prefix, and those devoid of it. Like
nouns, they cannot bear TAM inflection and fulfill the predicate function by
combining with the copula
g‹o›di
[11]
or with the verb
‹b›ik’uruƛa
‘be’.[12]
In Axaxdərə Akhvakh, adjectives in the role of noun dependent
or in predicate function do not show suffixal inflection, whereas nominalized
adjectives (i.e., adjectives occurring as the last word of a noun phrase) are
inflected for plural and take suffixed class
marks.[13]
In the absolute form, the
class marks suffixed to nominalized adjectives are M
-we
, F
-je
, N
-be
, HPL
-ji
, NPL
-re
, whereas in combination with overt
case markers, the class marks suffixed to nominalized adjectives are identical
to the ‘oblique stem markers’ found in the case inflection of some
nouns (M
-s̱u-
, F/N
-
λ
̱i-
,
HPL
-lo-
, NPL
-le- ~ -li-).
Ex. (4) illustrates an adjective with a gender-number prefix
(
‹b›ašada
‘old’) and an adjective devoid of gender-number prefix
(
č’ĩda
‘new’)
in the role of noun dependent (a-b), in predicate function (c-d), and
nominalized (e-h).
(4)
|
a.
|
de-de
|
b-ašada
|
mašina
|
o-x̱-ada.
|
|
|
1SG-ERG
|
N-old
|
car
|
N-sell-PFVASSINV
|
|
|
‘I sold the old
car.’
|
|
b.
|
de-de
|
č’ĩda
|
mašina
|
b-eχ-ada.
|
|
|
1SG-ERG
|
new
|
car
|
N-buy-PFVASSINV
|
|
|
‘I bought a new
car.’
|
|
c.
|
ha
|
mašinadi
|
r-ašada
|
gedi.
|
|
|
DEM
|
carPL
|
NPL-old
|
COPNPL
|
|
|
‘These cars are
old.’
|
|
d.
|
ha
|
mašinadi
|
č’ĩda
|
gedi.
|
|
|
DEM
|
carPL
|
new
|
COPNPL
|
|
|
‘These cars are
new.’
|
|
e.
|
de-de
|
b-ašada-be
|
o-x̱-ada.
|
|
|
1SG-ERG
|
N-old-N
|
N-sell-PFVASSINV
|
|
|
‘I sold the old
one.’
|
|
f.
|
de-de
|
č’ĩda-be
|
b-eχ-ada.
|
|
|
1SG-ERG
|
new-N
|
N-buy-PFVASSINV
|
|
|
‘I bought a new
one.’
|
|
g.
|
b-ašada-λ̱i-ga
|
eq̄-a!
|
|
|
N-old-ON-LAT
|
look at-IMP
|
|
|
‘Look at the old
one!’
|
|
h.
|
č’ĩda-λ̱i-ga
|
eq̄-a!
|
|
|
new-ON-LAT
|
look at-IMP
|
|
|
‘Look at the new
one!’
|
3.4. Verb
Inflection
Independent verb forms are inflected for TAM, polarity, and
gender-number agreement; TAM and polarity are conjointly expressed by
portemanteau markers. Assertive agreement (see section 3.4.3 below) is
morphologically distinct from gender-number agreement and occurs in one tense
only.
In addition to the synthetic forms listed in section 3.4.1, AD Akhvakh
has analytic verb forms with the copula
g‹o›di
or the verb
‹b›ik’uruƛa
‘be’ in auxiliary function.
3.4.1. TAM-Polarity Marking in
Independent Verb Forms
TAM/polarity inflection of verbs heading independent clauses
includes the following
possibilities:[14]
- perfective positive (-ari
or
-ada
, according to
‘assertive agreement’ – see section 3.4.3),
- perfective negative
(-iƛa),
- imperfective positive
(-ida),
- imperfective negative
(-ika),
- irrealis positive
(-iri),
- irrealis negative
(-iki),
- indirective past positive (M
-uwi
, F
-iwi
, N/NPL
-awi),[15]
- indirective past negative (M
-iƛ-uwi
, F
-iƛ-iwi
, N/NPL
-iƛ-awi),
- potential
(M/N/NPL
-uwa
, F
-iwa
, HPL
-oji),
- imperative
(-a),
- prohibitive
(-uba),
- optative positive
(-a-ƛ̱’a),
- optative negative
(-uba-ƛ̱’a),
- interrogative positive (M
-uwa
, F
-iwa
, N/NPL
-awa
, HPL
-aji),
- interrogative
negative (M
-uš-uwa
, F
-uš-iwa
, N/NPL
-uš-awa
, HPL
-uš-aji).
3.4.2.
Class Agreement in Verbal Inflection
Class agreement of verbs involves both prefixes and
suffixes, with two different kinds of conditioning:
- The presence of class
prefixes in verb forms
involves no grammatical conditioning. Verbs divide into two phonologically and
semantically arbitrary morphological classes, those that cannot occur without a
class prefix indexing the S or P argument (i.e., the argument encoded by an NP
in the absolute form), and those that never take such a
prefix.
- By contrast, the presence of class
suffixes indexing the S or P argument is conditioned by the grammatical
nature of the verb form. The rules governing the presence and the phonological
realization of class suffixes in verb forms are complex. In some verb forms,
class suffixes do not occur at all; in others, obligatory class agreement marks
merge with TAM/polarity markers; in a third group of verb forms, class suffixes
are optional, and when they are present they may appear as distinct segments, or
merge with TAM/polarity
markers.
The presence of class agreement marks in verb forms depends
therefore on a complex combination of lexical and grammatical factors, but the
agreement rule itself is always the same: whenever class marks are present in a
verb form, they invariably index an absolutive argument, i.e. an argument that
can be represented by an NP in the absolute form.
3.4.3. Assertive
Agreement
The perfective positive is the only tense in which, in
addition to class agreement with the absolutive argument, verbs express speech
act role distinctions, which however cannot be straightforwardly formulated in
terms of the traditional category of grammatical person (i.e.,
speaker
vs.
addressee vs.
others).[16]
There are two
possible endings for this tense, with basic allomorphs
-ada
(glossed
ASSINV for ‘assertor’s
involvement’) and
-ari
(glossed
PFV).
[17]
In contexts other than reported speech, the choice between
-ada
and
-ari
expresses a
1st person
(-ada) vs.
2nd/3rd person
(-ari) contrast in
declarative clauses, but
2nd person
(-ada) vs.
1st/3rd person
(-ari) contrast in questions, and
follows a split intransitive pattern. In the following chart, S
A
stands for ‘S argument of an intransitive verb triggering the choice of
-ada
in the same way as the A argument of
a transitive verb’:
(5)
|
Assertive agreement in the perfective positive
in AD Akhvakh
|
|
|
|
|
statements
|
questions
|
|
1st person A / S
A
|
-ada
|
-ari
|
|
2nd person A / S
A
|
-ari
|
-ada
|
|
3rd person A / S
A
|
-ari
|
-ari
|
|
no A / S
A
|
-ari
|
-ari
|
As indicated in this chart, transitive verbs invariably show
agreement with A (
-ada
with 1st person A
and
-ari
with 2nd/3rd person A in
statements,
-ada
with 2nd person A and
-ari
with 1st/3rd person A in questions),
whereas intransitive verbs divide into two semantically motivated classes:
S
A verbs agree with S in the same way as transitive verbs with A
(accusative alignment), whereas S
P verbs do not agree, and invariably
show the ending
-ari
(ergative alignment).
Ex. (6) & (7) illustrate assertive agreement with transitive verbs.
(6)
|
a.
|
de-de
|
kaʁa
|
q̄war-ada.
|
|
|
1SG-ERG
|
paper
|
write-PFVASSINV
|
|
|
‘I wrote a
letter.’
|
|
b.
|
me-de / hu-s̱w-e /
hu-λ̱-e
|
kaʁa
|
q̄war-ari.
|
|
|
2SG-ERG/DEM-OM-ERG /DEM-OF-ERG
|
paper
|
write-PFV
|
|
|
‘You / he / she wrote a
letter.’
|
|
c.
|
*de-de kaʁa
q̄war-ari.
|
|
d.
|
*me-de / *hu-s̱w-e / *hu-λ̱-e
kaʁa q̄war-ada.
|
(7)
|
a.
|
me-de
|
čũda
|
kaʁa
|
q̄war-ada?
|
|
|
2SG-ERG
|
when
|
paper
|
write-PFVASSINV
|
|
|
‘When did you write a
letter?’
|
|
b.
|
de-de / hu-s̱w-e /
hu-λ̱-e
|
čũda
|
kaʁa
|
q̄war-ari?
|
|
|
1SG-ERG / DEM-OM-ERG /
DEM-OF-ERG
|
when
|
paper
|
write-PFV
|
|
|
‘When did I / he / she write a
letter?’
|
|
c.
|
*me-de čũda kaʁa
q̄war-ari?
|
|
d.
|
*de-de / *hu-s̱w-e / *hu-λ̱-e
čũda kaʁa q̄war-ada?
|
In reported speech, the choice
between
-ari
and
-ada
in the reported clause has no direct relation with the person
value manifested by the NP in S or A role (which may depend on the deictic
shifts occurring in reported speech), and exclusively depends on the fact that
the A / S
A argument coincides or not with the person whose speech is
reported. In ex. (8a), the speaker coincides with the agent of the reported
event, but not with the person who asserted the reported clause, hence the
choice of
-ari
; in ex. (8b), the
person who asserted the reported clause is different from the speaker, but
coincides with the agent of the reported event, hence the choice of
-ada
.
(8)
|
a.
|
ek’wa-s̱w-e
|
eƛ̱’-ari
|
de-de
|
kaʁa
|
q̄war-ari
|
eƛ̱’-e.
|
|
|
man-OM-ERG
|
say-PFV
|
1SG-ERG
|
paper
|
write-PFV
|
say-CVB
|
|
|
‘The man said I wrote a
letter.’
|
|
b.
|
ek’wa-s̱w-e
|
eƛ̱’-ari
|
ĩ-s̱w-e
|
kaʁa
|
q̄war-ada.
|
|
|
man-OM-ERG
|
say-PFV
|
ANA-OM-ERG
|
paper
|
write-PFVASSINV
|
|
|
‘The man
i said he
i
wrote a letter.’
|
The division of Akhvakh intransitive verbs into two classes
according to their compatibility with the ending
-ada
in the perfective positive
transparently reflects the degree of control of the participant encoded as S.
Consequently, the precise function of the ending
-ada
is to encode coincidence between the
controller of the event and the assertor, i.e., the speech act participant
responsible for the assertion (the speaker in declarative speech acts, the
addressee in questions, the person whose speech is reported in reported
clauses). This is the reason why I propose the term ‘assertive
agreement’.[18]
3.4.4.
Participles
AD Akhvakh has four participles. Each of them is
characterized by a stem homonymous with one of the independent verb forms listed
above: perfective positive
-ada
),
perfective negative (
-iƛa
),
imperfective positive (-ida), and
imperfective negative (-ika). A more
detailed presentation of the participles will be given in section 5.
3.4.5. Dependent Verb
Forms
Strictly dependent verb forms include an infinitive
(-u(ruƛa)), a general converb (M
-o(ho), F
-e(he), N
-e, HPL
-i, NPL
-ere), a progressive converb (M
-ero, HPL
-eri, F/N/NPL
-ere), and several specialized converbs
expressing various semantic types of adverbial
subordination.[19]
AD Akhvakh also has a verbal noun (-e), which however is rarely
found with dependents treated like dependents of a verbal head. Contrary to the
verbal noun (or ‘masdar’) of other Andic languages – see
(Kibrik (ed.) 1996:180-2) on Godoberi, (Kibrik (ed.) 2001:523-9) on Bagvala),
the verbal noun of Akhvakh tends to behave like a de-verbal noun rather than an
inflected verb form, and is not productively used as the head of subordinate
clauses.
4. Akhvakh Morphosyntax and the
Domains of Finiteness
4.1. Finiteness and
Tense
In some languages, the presence of tense markers in verb
forms clearly correlates with finiteness as a grammatical feature of predicative
constructions. The problem in Akhvakh is that all verb forms are overtly marked
by an inflectional suffix, and inflectional suffixes are portemanteau markers
conflating aspecto-temporal and modal meanings, polarity, and sometimes
agreement too. The structure of Akhvakh verb forms does not involve a
morphological slot that could be straightforwardly characterized as reserved for
the expression of tense to the exclusion of other inflectional distinctions.
There is in Akhvakh no clear morphological evidence supporting a division of
verb forms into two subsets on the basis of tense marking. The semantic
specifications carried by the inflectional suffixes of dependent verb forms are
different from those carried by suffixes characteristic of independent verb
forms, but it is not possible to characterize them
globally as
‘reduced’ or ‘more rudimentary’. Note in particular that
(a) the
ada-,
iƛa-,
ida-
and
ika-
forms used as
participles express the same
perfective vs. imperfective distinction as
when used as heads of independent assertive clauses, and (b) the temporal
converbs, which are strictly dependent verb forms, express relative tense
distinctions more detailed than the tense specifications carried by independent
verb forms.
4.2. Finiteness and
Agreement
A striking particularity of Akhvakh is that there is no
simple correlation between the agreement morphology of verb forms and the
ability of predicative constructions to be used as independent clauses with
particular illocutionary values and/or to be involved in particular types of
complex structures.
The speech act role distinctions found in the perfective positive do not
correlate with a particular behavior that would distinguish the clauses headed
by a verb marked for this tense. Concerning class agreement, there is no simple
relationship between the way Akhvakh verb forms agree or not with their
absolutive argument, and their ability to head independent clauses, as can be
seen from the classification of AD Akhvakh verb forms according to the
presence/absence of suffixed class marks given in (9). In this chart, verb forms
are divided into those that have the ability to head independent clauses, and
those that are found in clauses involved in complex constructions only.
(9)
|
Suffixed class agreement markers in Akhvakh
verb forms
|
|
|
|
|
Independent verb forms
|
Dependent verb forms
|
|
a. Suffixes expressing obligatory class
agreement with more than two possible values
|
potential
indirective past
interrogative
|
general converb
|
|
b. Suffixes including an obligatory
HPL vs.
other classes
distinction, and compatible with additional suffixes
optionally expressing class agreement with other classes
|
perfective positive
-ada
imperfective positive
|
|
|
c. Suffixes including no obligatory class
agreement, but compatible with optional class marks
|
perfective negative
imperfective negative
|
progressive converb
similative converb
|
|
d. Suffixes expressing an obligatory
HPL vs.
other classes
distinction, but without the possibility of optional class
agreement with other classes
|
perfective positive
-ari
|
conditional converb
posterior converb
inceptive converb
|
|
e. Suffixes that never include marks of class
agreement
|
irrealis
irrealis negative
imperative
prohibitive
|
infinitive
verbal noun
verbal locative
simultaneous converb
immediate converbs
imminent converb
anterior converb
non-posterior converb
concessive converb
gradual converb
explicative converb
purposive converb
|
4.3.
The Expression of
the S/A Argument
4.3.1. The Expression of the
S/A Argument of Verbs in the Imperative
Incompatibility with canonical S/A NPs is a common
manifestation of nonfiniteness, and in many languages, imperatives pattern from
this point of view with dependent verb forms (Nikolaeva 2007b). Akhvakh has an
imperative and a prohibitive that are strictly addressee-oriented, but do not
differ from independent assertive verb forms with respect to the expression of
the S/A argument. Akhvakh is a ‘pro-drop’ language, in which NPs
representing arguments are not required syntactically, and pronouns occur in
argumental roles only if there is a possibility of ambiguity, or to express
emphasis. Similarly, imperatives and prohibitives do not necessarily combine
with second person pronouns in A/S role, but there is no ban on their presence
– ex. (4).
(10)
|
a.
|
(me-ne / ušti)
|
čab-a!
|
|
|
2SG-ABS / 2PL
|
wash-IMP
|
|
|
‘Wash!’
|
|
|
b.
|
(me-de / ušt-e)
|
riƛ̱’i
|
q̄’am-a!
|
|
|
2SG-ERG / 2PL-ERG
|
meat
|
eat-IMP
|
|
|
‘Eat the meat!’
|
Note in particular that imperatives and prohibitives of
transitive verbs are compatible with a second person pronoun in the ergative
case, which excludes analyzing the second person pronoun accompanying
imperatives or prohibitives as a kind of vocative.
4.3.2. The Expression of the
S/A Argument of Verbs in the Infinitive
The infinitive of Akhvakh may occur in control constructions
in which its S/A argument is obligatorily left unexpressed, and is semantically
identified to an argument of the main verb, as in ex. (11).
(11)
|
a.
|
di-ƛa
|
[ʕĩk’o
|
b-ix̱-uruƛa]
|
ĩd-iƛa.
|
|
|
1SG-DAT
|
hen
|
N-catch-INF
|
be_able-PFVNEG
|
|
|
‘I was not able to catch the
hen.’
|
|
b.
|
moḻa
|
w-ašl-ēri
|
[ži-we-da
|
ʁad-u-k’-ada
|
hala
|
b-uq̄’-uruƛa].
|
|
|
Molla
|
M-begin-IRR[20]
|
ana-m-int
|
PREV-M-sit-PFVPTCP
|
branch
|
N-cut-INF
|
|
|
‘Molla started cutting the branch on
which he was sitting.’
|
However, this behavior is triggered by some of the verbs
taking infinitival complements (in ex. (5),
ĩdunuƛa
‘be able’
and
‹b›ašlōruƛa
‘begin’), and does not constitute an intrinsic property of the
infinitive itself. For example,
kwĩλuruƛa
‘want’ and
bužuruƛa
‘believe’ combine with infinitival complement clauses in which all
the arguments of the verb in the infinitive can be expressed without any
co-reference constraint – ex. (12). Note in particular that, with
infinitives of transitive verbs, the fact that the S/A argument occurs in the
ergative case excludes an analysis in terms of ‘raising to
object’.
(12)
|
a.
|
di-ƛa
|
kwĩλ-e
|
goƛa
|
[me-de
|
ha-be
|
eƛ̱’-uruƛa].
|
|
|
1SG-DAT
|
want-CVBN
|
COPEGN
|
2SG-ERG
|
DEM-N
|
say-INF
|
|
|
‘I don’t want you to say
this.’
|
|
b.
|
de-ne
|
buž-ero
|
guƛo
|
[χwe-ƛa
|
ʕara
|
mic̱’i
|
b-eq’-uruƛa].
|
|
|
1SG-ABS
|
believe-PROGM
|
COPNEGM
|
dog-DAT
|
Arabic
|
language
|
N-know-INF
|
|
|
‘I don’t believe that the dog knows
Arabic.’
|
The same applies to infinitives heading adverbial clauses of purpose
– ex. (13).
(13)
|
a.
|
me-de
|
duʕa
|
gwij-a
|
[hu-s̱w-e
|
če
|
hula
|
m-ič-unuƛa]!
|
|
|
2SG-ERG
|
prayer
|
do-IMP
|
DEM-OM-ERG
|
one
|
thing
|
N-find-INF[21]
|
|
|
‘Pray that he will find
something!’
|
|
b.
|
de-de
|
či
|
gw-īri
|
[ãdo-lo-ƛa
|
de-ne
|
šoda
|
gwi-s̱a
|
b-eq’-uruƛa]?
|
|
|
1SG-ERG
|
what
|
do-IRR[22]
|
personPL-OHPL-DAT
|
1sg-ABS
|
good
|
COPM-COMP
|
N-know-INF
|
|
|
‘What should I do so that people know
that I am a good person?’
|
It is also worth noting that, with the exception of a very limited
number of verbs forming with their infinitival complement a control
construction, as in ex. (11) above, even when the S/A argument of the infinitive
is not overtly expressed, it is not necessarily identified to an argument of the
main verb. Depending on the context, an arbitrary interpretation is always
possible. For example, the sentence in ex. (14) has two possible readings; most
of the time, an unexpressed argument in the construction of an infinitive
complement of
kwĩλuruƛa
‘want’ is identified with the dative argument of
kwĩλuruƛa, but in the text
from which this sentence has been extracted, it is clear from the context that
an arbitrary interpretation was intended.
(14)
|
ilise-ƛa
|
kwĩl-e
|
goƛa
|
[moḻa rasadi
|
šakila
|
r-eq̄-ōruƛa].
|
|
Ilise-DAT
|
want-CVBN
|
COPNEGN
|
Molla Rasadi
|
picturePL
|
NPL-draw-INF[23]
|
|
1. ‘Ilise does not want to take pictures
of Molla Rasadi.’
|
|
2. ‘Ilise does not want people taking
pictures of Molla Rasadi.’
|
In other words, in general, the interpretation of missing arguments in
infinitival clauses is a pragmatic mechanism which does not differ from the
interpretation of missing arguments in independent clauses.
4.3.3. The Expression of the
S/A Argument of Verbs in a Converbal Form
With the only exception of the progressive converb (which
differs from all the other converbs of Akhvakh in its syntactic properties and
mainly occurs as an element of analytic verb forms), a general property of the
converbs is that their arguments can always be expressed exactly in the same way
as in independent clauses. The ability of the converbs to combine with an NP in
S/A role whose referent does not coincide with any of the arguments of the main
verb is illustrated in ex. (15) by complex sentences involving the negative form
of the posterior converb (a), the immediate converb (b), the imminent converb
(c), the conditional converb (d), and the explicative converb (e).
(15)
|
a.
|
[maħmaʕali-de
|
reƛ’a
|
dan-iƛ-eλ̱i]
|
imo-de
|
eƛ̱’-awi,
|
“w-ãʔ-a!”.
|
|
|
Mehmet-Ali-ERG
|
hand
|
draw_away-NEG-POST
|
fatherO-ERG
|
say-INDPSTN
|
M-go-IMP
|
|
|
‘As Mehmet-Ali insisted (lit. did not
draw away his hand), his father said, “Go!”.’
|
|
b.
|
[λ̱ẽ
|
ãχw-ik’ena]
|
χĩk’a
|
šãgi-ga
|
t’am-a!
|
|
|
water
|
boil-immed
|
dumplingPL
|
cooking-pot-LAT
|
put-IMP
|
|
|
‘As soon as the water boils, put the
dumplings in the cooking-pot!’
|
|
c.
|
[c̱’ari
|
c̱’-ēdaλ̱a]
|
χam-e
|
b-oč’il-āri.
|
|
|
rain
|
fall-IMMIN[24]
|
mow-VN
|
N-end-PFV
[25]
|
|
|
‘The hay-harvest was up just before it
rained.’
|
|
d.
|
[me-de
|
ĩc̱’o-ge
|
ƛ’a
|
q̄ãdiro
|
gin-aj-e
|
m-ič-ala]
|
|
|
2SG-ERG
|
door-ESS
|
on.ESS
|
sickle
|
hang-CAUS-CVBN
|
N-be-CON[26]
|
|
|
is̱i
|
eša
|
m-īda
|
wolidi.
|
|
|
1PLE
|
away
|
HPL-go.IPFV[27]
|
COPHPL
|
|
|
‘If you have hung a sickle on the door,
we will go away.’
|
|
e.
|
[imiχi
|
b-uq-eregu]
|
ʕazi
|
gw-ēre
|
godi.
|
|
|
donkey
|
N-disappear-EXPLIC
|
complaint
|
do-PROG[28]
|
COPN
|
|
|
‘He is complaining that the donkey has
disappeared.’
|
A missing argument in a clause headed by a specialized converb may be
identified to an argument or the main verb, but the progressive converb is the
only one whose construction obligatorily involves a missing argument that must
be identified to an argument of the main verb. The general rule is that the
identification of missing arguments in the construction of specialized converbs
is a purely pragmatic phenomenon, which does not put into play syntactic
constraints. Depending on the context, a missing argument in the construction of
a converb can always be identified to a speech act participant, or to any other
salient referent, as illustrated by ex. (16).
(16)
|
[raƛa
|
ƛ̱’-ũ-k’-ideλ̱i ]
|
če
|
b-ašida
|
šãƛ’e-la
|
ĩč’-ada
|
χ̄otala
|
harigw-iri.
|
|
at_night
|
PREV-M-sleep-SIMULT
|
one
|
N-white
|
cloth-ADD
|
wear-PFV
PTCP
|
ghost
|
see-IRR
|
|
‘At night while sleeping he saw a ghost
wearing a white cloth.’
|
The translation given in ex. (16) corresponds to the interpretation of
this sentence in the context in which I have found it, but the same sentence in
different contexts could equally be interpreted as ‘While sleeping I saw a
ghost’, ‘While I slept he saw a ghost’, ‘While he slept
I saw a ghost’, ‘While hei slept hej saw a
ghost’, etc. The only constraint is that the missing argument of
‘sleep’ must be masculine singular, since the converbal form
ƛ̱’ũk’ideλ̱i
shows masculine singular agreement; the interpretation of the missing argument
of ‘see’ is totally open, since the form
harigwiri
includes no agreement mark,
and there is no co-reference or disjoint reference constraint between the
missing argument of the converb and any of the arguments of the main
verb.
5. Participles
5.1. The Notion of Participle
in Traditional Grammar
In languages in which the inflectional approach to finiteness is not
problematic, the forms traditionally labeled ‘participles’ have the
following properties:
- participles are verb forms in the sense that, with respect
to their ‘internal syntax’ (i.e., the internal structure of the
phrases they head), they have the same properties as verb forms heading
independent clauses;
- participles are non-finite
verb forms, i.e., they cannot head independent clauses, and this inability is
correlated with the lack of morphological distinctions characteristic of the
independent verb forms of the same
language;
- participles have the ‘external
syntax’ of adjectives: taken as a whole, clauses headed by participles are
syntactically equivalent to adjective phrases; they can fulfill the roles of
noun dependent and non-verbal predicate, or undergo nominalization, in the same
way as adjective phrases;
- in all of the roles
accessible to adjective phrases, the verb form heading a participial clause
shows the same behavior (in particular, the same inflectional characteristics)
as the head of an adjective phrase fulfilling the same
role;
- semantically, participial clauses modify
the noun they depend on by identifying it to an unexpressed constituent of the
participial
clause.
5.2.
Participles and Independent Verb Forms in Akhvakh
If participles are defined as verb forms involved in a
particular type of relativization
strategy,[29]
there is no difficulty
in recognizing four participles in Akhvakh (perfective positive, perfective
negative, imperfective positive, and imperfective negative). This means that
these four verb forms occur in pre-nominal relative clauses, showing at the same
time the same characteristics as attributive adjectives with respect to their
relation to a head noun.[30]
Such
relative clauses can be used in predicate function or nominalized in the same
way as adjective phrases, and the verb forms that head them take agreement
suffixes and case inflection exactly like adjectives. What is particular in the
case of Akhvakh is that none of the verb forms found in participial relatives is
specialized in participle function. In Akhvakh, the set of verb forms occurring
as heads of relative clauses with a typically participial behavior is a proper
subset of the set of verb forms occurring as heads of independent clauses.
Moreover, when used as heads of independent clauses, the verb forms in question
do not show properties that would distinguish them from the independent verb
forms that cannot function as participles.
Note however that,
in constructional terms, participial relative
clauses are not entirely identical to independent clauses headed by the same
verb forms, in spite of the fact that they may include the same NPs with the
same case marking. The point is that relative clauses are strictly head-final,
whereas the verbal head of an independent clause has no fixed position.
In addition to that, with one of the four participles of Akhvakh (the
perfective positive, see section 5.5) the participle is formally identical to an
independent verb form carrying the same TAM and polarity specifications, but is
not involved in the mechanism of assertive agreement characterizing the same
form in independent clauses.[31]
Here again, the necessity to complete the morphological observations by a
constructional approach is patent.
5.3. The Imperfective Positive
Participle
Verb forms marked by the imperfective positive suffix
-ida
occur as heads not only of
independent assertive clauses, as in ex. (17a), but also of relative clauses, as
in ex. (17b). There is no overt mark of the dependent status of the relative
clause, and there is no overt indication of the relativized role either. The
only difference between such a relative clause and an independent clause with a
missing term lending itself to an anaphorical or arbitrary reading is the
obligatory final position of the verb in the relative clause, as illustrated by
the fact that a sequence such as
du-ƛa
kw-ī̃da b-eχ-uruƛa
is acceptable as an
independent clause with a missing argument anaphorically identified to a
discursively salient entity – ex. (17c), but not as a relative clause
– ex. (17d).
(17)
|
a.
|
du-ƛa
|
kw-ī̃da
|
ha
|
č’ili
|
b-eχ-uruƛa.
|
|
|
2SGO-DAT
|
want-IPFV[32]
|
DEM
|
house
|
N-buy-INF
|
|
|
‘You want to buy this
house.’
|
|
b.
|
[du-ƛa
|
b-eχ-uruƛa
|
kw-ī̃da]
|
č’ili
|
reš̱eda
|
godi.
|
|
|
2SGO-DAT
|
N-buy-INF
|
want-IPVFPTCP
|
house
|
nice
|
COPN
|
|
|
‘The house you want to buy is
nice.’
|
|
c.
|
du-ƛa
|
kw-ī̃da
|
b-eχ-uruƛa.
|
|
|
2SGO-DAT
|
want-IPFV
|
N-buy-INF
|
|
|
‘You want to buy
it.’
|
|
d.
|
*[du-ƛa kw-ĩda b-eχ-uruƛa]
č’ili ...
|
|
|
intended: ‘The house you want to buy
…’
|
Ex. (18) & (19) compare relative clauses in the imperfective
positive modifying a noun with the corresponding free relatives. In ex. (18b),
the free relative fulfills a role requiring the zero-marked absolute case,
whereas in ex. (19b), it fulfills a role requiring an overt case mark.
Comparison with ex. (4) above shows that, in both cases, the suffixes that
attach to the participle (a class suffix in (18b), an oblique stem marker
followed by the case marker in (19b)) are identical to those that would attach
to nominalized adjectives in the same contexts.
(18)
|
a.
|
[du-ƛa
|
b-eχ-uruƛa
|
kw-ī̃da]
|
č’ili
|
reš̱eda
|
godi.
|
|
|
2SGO-DAT
|
N-buy-INF
|
want-IPFVPTCP
|
house
|
nice
|
COPN
|
|
|
‘The house you want to buy is
nice.’
|
|
b.
|
[du-ƛa
|
b-eχ-uruƛa
|
kw-ī̃da]-be
|
reš̱eda
|
godi.
|
|
|
2SGO-DAT
|
N-buy-INF
|
want-IPFVPTCP-N
|
nice
|
COPN
|
|
|
‘The one you want to buy is
nice.’
|
(19)
|
a.
|
eq̄-a
|
[di-ƛa
|
b-eχ-uruƛa
|
kw-ī̃da]
|
č’ili-λ̱i-ga!
|
|
|
look_at-IMP
|
1SGO-DAT
|
N-buy-INF
|
want-IPFVPTCP
|
house-ON-LAT
|
|
|
‘Look at the house I want to
buy!’
|
|
b.
|
eq̄-a
|
[di-ƛa
|
b-eχ-uruƛa
|
kw-ī̃da]-λ̱i-ga!
|
|
|
look_at-IMP
|
1SGO-DAT
|
N-buy-INF
|
want-IPFVPTCP-ON-LAT
|
|
|
‘Look at the one I want to
buy!’
|
5.4. The Imperfective Negative
Participle
As illustrated by ex. (20) & (21), verb forms marked by
the imperfective negative suffix
-ika
share this ability to occur both in independent clauses and in participial
relatives.
(20)
|
a.
|
mik’eli
|
heres̱i
|
m-ač-ika.
|
|
|
childPL
|
lie
|
N-tell-IPFVNEG[33]
|
|
|
‘Children do not tell
lies.’
|
|
b.
|
heres̱i
|
m-ač-ika.
|
|
|
lie
|
N-tell-IPFVNEG
|
|
|
‘I don’t tell lies.’,
‘You don’t tell lies.’, ‘S/he doesn’t tell
lies.’, etc.
|
|
c.
|
di-ƛa
|
kw-ī̃da
|
[heres̱i
|
m-ač-ika]
|
mik’eli.
|
|
|
1SGO-DAT
|
like-IPFV
|
lie
|
N-tell-IPFVNEGPTCP
|
childPL
|
|
|
‘I like children who do not tell
lies.’
|
|
d.
|
di-ƛa
|
kw-ī̃da
|
[heres̱i
|
m-ač-iki ]-ji.
|
|
|
1SGO-DAT
|
like-IPFV
|
lie
|
N-tell-IPFVNEGPTCP-HPL
|
|
|
‘I like those who do not tell
lies.’
|
(21)
|
a.
|
de-ne
|
buž-ida
|
[heres̱i
|
m-ač-ika]
|
ãdo-lo-ga.
|
|
|
1SG-ABS
|
believe-IPFV
|
lie
|
N-tell-IPFVNEGPTCP
|
personPL-OHPL-LAT
|
|
|
‘I believe people who do not tell
lies.’
|
|
d.
|
de-ne
|
buž-ida
|
[heres̱i
|
m-ač-iko]-lo-ga.
|
|
|
1SG-ABS
|
believe-IPFV
|
lie
|
N-tell-IPFVNEGPTCP-OHPL-LAT
|
|
|
‘I believe those who do not tell
lies.’
|
5.5. The Perfective Positive
Participle
The suffix of the perfective positive participle
-ada
is identical to one of the two
suffixes marking the perfective positive in independent clauses. The difference
is however that, in independent clauses,
-ada
implies a 1st person A/SA
argument in declarative clauses and a 2nd person A/SA argument in
questions, and the same TAM value is marked by the suffix
-ari
if this condition is not met, whereas
relative clauses ignore this agreement mechanism, and uniformly mark the
perfective positive with
-ada
– ex.
(22).
(22)
|
a.
|
de-de
|
lãga
|
r-eχ-ada.
|
|
|
1SG-ERG
|
sheepPL
|
NPL-buy-PFVASSINV
|
|
|
‘I bought sheep.’
|
|
b.
|
lãga
|
r-eχ-ada.
|
|
|
sheepPL
|
NPL-buy-PFVASSINV
|
|
|
‘I bought sheep.’, ‘We bought
sheep.’
|
|
c.
|
ek’wa-s̱w-e
|
lãga
|
r-eχ-ari.
|
|
|
man-OM-ERG
|
sheepPL
|
NPL-buy-PFV
|
|
|
‘The man bought
sheep.’
|
|
d.
|
lãga
|
r-eχ-ari.
|
|
|
sheepPL
|
NPL-buy-PFV
|
|
|
‘You bought sheep.’, ‘S/he
bought sheep.’, ‘They bought sheep.’
|
|
e.
|
di-ƛa
|
harigw-iƛa
|
[lãga
|
r-eχ-ada]
|
ek’wa.
|
|
|
1SGO-DAT
|
see-PFVNEG
|
sheepPL
|
NPL-buy-PFVPTCP
|
man
|
|
|
‘I did not see the man who bought
sheep.’
|
|
f.
|
di-ƛa
|
harigw-iƛa
|
[lãga
|
r-eχ-ada]-we.
|
|
|
1SGO-DAT
|
see-PFVNEG
|
sheepPL
|
NPL-buy-PFVPTCP-M
|
|
|
‘I did not see the one who bought
sheep.’
|
|
g.
|
eq̄-a
|
[lãga
|
r-eχ-ada]
|
ek’wa-s̱u-ga!
|
|
|
look_at-IMP
|
sheepPL
|
NPL-buy-PFVPTCP
|
man-OM-LAT
|
|
|
‘Look at the man who bought
sheep!’
|
|
h.
|
eq̄-a
|
[lãga
|
r-eχ-ada]-s̱u-ga!
|
|
|
look_at-IMP
|
sheepPL
|
NPL-buy-PFVPTCP-OM-LAT
|
|
|
‘Look at the one who bought
sheep!’
|
5.6. The Perfective Negative
Participle
As illustrated by ex. (23), the situation with perfective
negative
-iƛa
is exactly the same as
with imperfective positive
-ida
or
imperfective negative
-ika
.
(23)
|
a.
|
ha
|
ek’wa
|
w-ošq̄-iƛa.
|
|
|
DEM
|
man
|
M-work-PFVNEG[34]
|
|
|
‘This man did not
work.’
|
|
b.
|
[w-ošq̄-iƛa
|
ek’wa]
|
du
|
wac̱i
|
gudi.
|
|
|
M-work-PFVNEGPTCP
|
man
|
2SGO
|
brother
|
COPM
|
|
|
‘The man who did not work is your
brother.’
|
|
c.
|
[w-ošq̄-iƛa]-we
|
du
|
wac̱i
|
gudi.
|
|
|
M-work-PFVNEGPTCP-M
|
2SGO
|
brother
|
COPM
|
|
|
‘The one who did not work is your
brother.’
|
|
d.
|
ači
|
o-x̱-uba
|
[w-ošq̄-iƛa]
|
ek’wa-s̱u-ga!
|
|
|
money
|
N-give-PROH
|
M-work-PFVNEGPTCP
|
man-OM-LAT
|
|
|
‘Don’t give money to the man who
did not work!’
|
|
e.
|
ači
|
o-x̱-uba
|
[w-ošq̄-iƛa]-s̱u-ga!
|
|
|
money
|
N-give-PROH
|
M-work-PFVNEGPTCP-OM-LAT
|
|
|
‘Don’t give money to the one who
did not work!’
|
5.7. Accessibility to
Relativization
Ex. (24) illustrates the fact that the participial relatives
presented in sections 5.3 to 5.6 can be used to relativize any term (argument or
adjunct) of the construction of the verb, and also genitives.
(24)
|
a.
|
[jaše-ga
|
kemeti
|
o-x̱-ada]
|
aḵ’i
|
|
|
girl-LAT
|
sweets
|
N-give-PFVPTCP
|
woman
|
|
|
‘the woman who gave sweets to the
girl’
|
|
b.
|
[aḵ’o-de
|
kemeti
|
o-x̱-ada]
|
jaše
|
|
|
womanO-ERG
|
sweets
|
N-give-PFVPTCP
|
girl
|
|
|
‘the girl to whom the woman gave
sweets’
|
|
c.
|
[aḵ’o-de
|
jaše-ga
|
o-x̱-ada]
|
kemeti
|
|
|
womanO-ERG
|
girl-LAT
|
N-give-PFVPTCP
|
sweets
|
|
|
‘the sweets that the woman gave to the
girl’
|
|
d.
|
[de-de
|
ruša
|
b-uq̄’-ida]
|
ʕãžite
|
|
|
1SG-ERG
|
tree
|
N-cut-IPFVPTCP
|
axe
|
|
|
‘the axe with which I am cutting the
tree’
|
|
e.
|
[ek’wa
|
ʁad-u-k’-ada]
|
hala
|
|
|
man
|
PREV-M-sit-PFVPTCP
|
branch
|
|
|
‘the branch on which the man was
sitting’
|
|
f.
|
[jaše
|
j-ā̃da]
|
žo
|
|
|
girl
|
F-go.PFVPTCP[35]
|
day
|
|
|
‘the day when the girl went
away’
|
|
g.
|
[imiχi
|
b-uq-ada]
|
ek’wa
|
|
|
donkey
|
N-disappear-PFVPTCP
|
man
|
|
|
‘the man whose donkey has
disappeared’
|
5.8. Non-Restrictive
Participial Relatives
Ex. (25) shows that, in Akhvakh, participial relatives are
not necessarily restrictive.
(25)
|
a.
|
[ha
|
χ
oba
|
gw-ēda]
|
ʕosma-ƛa
|
gaza
|
b-iχ̄w-iƛ-awi.
|
|
|
DEM
|
mill
|
make-PFVPTCP[36]
|
Osman-DAT
|
nothing
|
N-remain-NEG-INPSTN
|
|
|
‘Nothing remained to Osman who had built
this mill.’
|
|
b.
|
[ʕumi-λ̱i
|
beča-ga
|
w-ī̃ƛa]
|
ħusejni
|
w-oƛ-ari.
|
|
|
life-ON.ESS
|
moutain-LAT
|
M-go.PFVNEGPTCP[37]
|
Huseyn
|
M-take-PFV[38]
|
|
|
‘They took with them Huseyn who had not
gone to the mountain ever in his life.’
|
|
c.
|
q̄arodi-lo-de
|
[ĩc̱’o-q̄e
|
ʁad-u-k’-ada]
|
moḻa
|
w-ux̱-uwi.
|
|
|
guardianPL-OHPL-ERG
|
door-ESS
|
PREV-M-sit-PFVPTCP
|
Molla
|
M-catch-INDPSTM[39]
|
|
|
‘The guardians caught Molla who was
sitting at the door.’
|
5.9.
Discussion
Akhvakh has participial clauses, i.e. clauses headed by a
verb form behaving like an adjective with respect to the insertion of the phrase
it heads into a broader construction. Participial clauses share with clauses
headed by strictly dependent verb forms (infinitive or converbs) the obligatory
final position of the verb, but none of the forms found as heads of participial
clauses is specialized in this function: all of them also occur in independent
assertive or interrogative clauses.
The case of the perfective positive is particularly interesting. As in
the other cases, the verb form heading a participial clause in the perfective
positive is not morphologically marked as specialized in participle function,
but in constructional terms, there is a clear distinction between independent
clauses in the perfective positive, in which the inflectional suffix of the verb
can be
-ada
or
-ari
according to the rule of assertive
agreement (see section 3.4.3), and participial clauses in the perfective
positive, in which
-ada
is the only
possibility.
In order to avoid contradictions and/or circularity in the description
of such situations, it is crucial to admit that the definitions of
construction types are logically anterior to the definitions of
form
types
. Very often, the recognition of a type of construction is ensured by
the morphological nature of its head, but the formal identification of a
construction does not necessarily rely on the presence of a word belonging to a
given morphological type. In Akhvakh, defining participial clauses as clauses
headed by a participle would not be correct, since Akhvakh has no form
specialized in participle function. The definition of
participial clause
must be posited first, and participles can be defined then as forms fulfilling
the predicate function in participial clauses, which does not exclude that the
same forms may occur in other functions too.
6. Conclusion
There is nothing exceptional in the existence of verb forms
fulfilling the predicate function both in independent assertive or interrogative
clauses and in participial clauses, and the historical source of such situations
is well-known. A scenario attested in many languages whose history is documented
or reconstructed with a high degree of plausibility is that such forms
originally were specialized participles. Given their adjectival nature,
participles can be used in adjectival predication, and adjectival predications
involving participles tend to undergo evolutions blurring the distinction with
verbal predication: if a copula is originally present, it may be deleted, or
fuse with the participle, becoming thus a TAM/agreement affix; if the case
marking of the arguments of a participle used as an adjectival predicate differs
from that found in verbal predication proper, it may be readjusted; a similar
readjustment may concern constraints on constituent order too, if adjectival
predication with a participle in predicate function originally involves
constraints different from those observed in verbal predication proper,
etc.
Nakh-Daghestanian languages provide ample evidence that such processes
have been very active in the history of this language family. What makes the
case of Akhvakh particularly interesting is that, in its present state, this
language has no specialized participles at all, and at the same time clearly
possesses a clause type identifiable as a participial clause.
I have tried to show in sections 4 & 5 that, in several respects,
Akhvakh has particularities hardly compatible with the traditional approach to
finiteness. The participial clauses analyzed in section 5 are a clear case of
nonfinite clauses including no nonfinite form. The Akhvakh data shows that a
very common type of historical process (the integration of participles into the
paradigm of verb forms heading independent assertive or interrogative clauses)
may result in a situation that necessitates positing the notion of participial
clause (defined in constructional terms) as logically anterior to the notion of
participial form.
Acknowledgements
I am grateful to the
Linguistic Discovery readers for
very useful comments on previous versions of this article.
Abbreviations
1SG: 1st person singular
|
ERG: ergative
|
N: singular non-human (neuter)
|
2SG: 2nd person singular
|
ESS: essive
|
NEG: negation
|
1PLE: 1st person plural
exclusive
|
INDPST: indirective past
|
NPL: non-human (neuter) plural
|
1PLI: 1st person plural
inclusive
|
EXPLIC: explicative converb
|
O: oblique stem
|
2PL: 2nd person plural
|
F: singular human feminine
|
OPT: optative
|
ABS: absolutive
|
GEN: genitive
|
PFV: perfective
|
ADD: additive particle
|
HPL: human plural
|
PFVNEG: perfective negative
|
ANA: anaphoric pronoun
|
IMMED: immediate converb
|
PL: plural
|
ASSINV: assertor’s
involvement
|
IMMIN: imminent converb
|
POST: posterior converb
|
CAUS: causative
|
IMP: imperative
|
POT: potential
|
COMP: complementizer
|
INESS: inessive
|
PREV: preverb*
|
COND: conditional converb
|
INF: infinitive
|
PROG: progressive converb
|
COP: copula
|
IPFV: imperfective
|
PROH: prohibitive
|
COPNEG: negative copula
|
IPFVNEG: imperfective negative
|
PTCP: participle
|
CVB: general converb
|
IRR: irrealis
|
SG: singular
|
DAT: dative
|
LAT: lative
|
SIMULT: simultaneous converb
|
DEM: demonstrative
|
M: singular human masculine
|
VN: verbal noun
|
EL: elative
|
|
|
*A very limited number of Akhvakh verbs have a discontinuous
root the two segments of which are separated by a class agreement mark. Eight
such verbs occur in my data. In the glosses, the English equivalent of their
lexical meaning is given as the gloss of the second segment, and the first
segment is glossed
prev, but this is purely
conventional, and ‘preverb’ must be understood here as ‘first
segment of a discontinuous verb root’. Akhvakh has nothing comparable to
Russian or Georgian preverbation.
References
Bisang, W. 2007. Categories that make finiteness: discreteness from
a functional perspective and some of its repercussions. In Nikolaeva, I. (ed.),
Finiteness, 115-137. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Comrie, B. & M. Polinsky. 1999. Form and function in syntax:
Relative clauses in Tsez. In Darnell M., E. Moravcsik, F. Newmeyer, M. Noonan,
& K. Wheatley (eds.), Functionalism and Formalism in Linguistics, 77-91.
Amsterdam / Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Creissels, D. 2008a. Person variations in Akhvakh verb morphology:
functional motivation and origin of an uncommon pattern. Sprachtypologie und
Universalienforchung 61-4.309-325. doi:10.1524/stuf.2008.0027
-----. 2008b. Remarks on so-called “conjunct/disjunct”
systems. Paper delivered at the Syntax of the World’s Languages III
conference. Berlin.
-----. To appear. Specialized converbs and adverbial subordination
in Axaxdərə Akhvakh. In Bril, I. (ed.), Clause-hierarchy and
clause-linking, syntax and pragmatics.
Cristofaro, S. 2007. Deconstructing categories: finiteness in a
functional-typological perspective. In Nikolaeva, I. (ed.), Finiteness, 91-114.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Curnow, T. 2002a. Conjunct/disjunct marking in Awa Pit. Linguistics
40-3.611-627. doi:10.1515/ling.2002.025
-----. 2002b. Conjunct/disjunct systems in Barbacoan languages.
Santa Barbara Papers in Linguistics 11. 3-12.
DeLancey S. 1986. Evidentiality and volitionality in Tibetan. In
Chafe, W. & J. Nichols (eds.), Evidentiality: the Linguistic Coding of
Epistemology, 203-213. Norwood NJ: Academic Press.
-----. 1990. Ergativity and the cognitive model of event structure
in Lhasa Tibetan. Cognitive Linguistics 1-3.289-321. doi:10.1515/cogl.1990.1.3.289
-----. 1992. The Historical status of the conjunct/disjunct
pattern. Acta Linguistica Hafniensa 25.39-42. doi:10.1080/03740463.1992.10412277
Dickinson, C. 2000. Mirativity in Tsafiki. Studies in Language
24-2.379-421. doi:10.1075/sl.24.2.06dic
Hale, A. 1980. Person markers: finite conjunct and disjunct forms
in Newari. In Trail R. (ed.), Papers in Southeast Asian Linguistics 7.95-106.
Canberra: Pacific Linguistics.
Hargreaves, D. 2005. Agency and intentional action in Kathmandu
Newar. Himalayan Linguistics 5.1-48.
Kalinina, E. & N. Sumbatova. 2007. Clause structure and verbal
forms in Nakh-Daghestanian languages. In Nikolaeva, I. (ed.), Finiteness,
183-249. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kibrik, A. E. 1985. Towards a typology of ergativity. In Nichols,
J. & A. Woodbury (eds.), Grammar inside and outside the clause, 268-324.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
-----. (ed.). 1996. Godoberi. München: LINCOM
EUROPA.
-----. (ed.). 2001. Bagvalinskij jazyk. Grammatika, teksty,
slovari. Moskva: IMLI RAN, “Nasledie”.
Loughnane, R. 2007. Expanding the typology of evidentiality: the
participatory/factual in Oksapmin. Paper delivered at the ALT 7 conference.
Paris.
Magomedbekova, Z.M. 1967. Axvaxskij jazyk (grammatičeskij
analiz, teksty, slovar’). Tbilisi: Mecniereba.
Magomedova, P & I. Abdulaeva. 2007. Axvaxsko-russkij
slovar’. Maxačkala: Dagestanskij Naučnyj Centr Rossiskoj
Akademii Nauk.
Magometov, A. 1982. Megebskij dialekt darginskogo jazyka. Tbilisi:
Mecniereba.
Nikolaeva, I. 2007a. Introduction. In Nikolaeva, I. (ed.),
Finiteness, 1-19. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
-----. 2007b. Constructional economy and nonfinite independent
clauses. In Nikolaeva, I. (ed.), Finiteness, 138-180. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Nikolaeva, I. (ed.). 2007. Finiteness. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Rebuschi, G. 1984. Structure de l’énoncé en
basque. Paris: SELAF.
Sells, P. 2007. Finiteness in non-transformational syntactic
frameworks. In Nikolaeva, I. (ed.), Finiteness, 59-88.
[1]
In general, I use
Akhvakh as the term most commonly found in the literature for the
language in question, but when I quote Russian terms,
axvaxskij occurs as
the transliteration of Russian
ахвахский.
[2]
The other Andic
languages are Andi, Bagvala, Botlikh, Chamala, Godoberi, Karata, and Tindi. None
of them has a particularly close relationship to Akhvakh. Andic languages are
traditionally grouped with Avar and Tsezic languages into a single branch of the
Northeast Caucasian family. The other branches of the Northeast Caucasian family
are Lak, Dargi (or Dargwa), Lezgi, Khinalug (sometimes considered a marginal
member of the Lezgi branch), and Nakh.
[3]
Judging from
(Magomedbekova 1967) and (Magomedova & Abdulaeva 2007), the variety of
Akhvakh spoken in
Axaxdərə does not
differ significantly from the varieties of Northern Akhvakh spoken in the
Axvaxskij Rajon, and this judgment was confirmed without any reservation by
Indira Abdulaeva, co-author of the Akhvakh-Russian dictionary and a native
speaker of Northern Akhvakh herself, who spent one week in
Axaxdərə while I was carrying field
work there in April 2008. I have been able to find no precision about the time
when Akhvakh migrants began to settle in
Axaxdərə, but there are still in
Axaxdərə old people who were born in
Daghestan, and whose parents migrated to Azerbaijan at the end of the second
world war, when the economic situation in Daghestan was particularly
difficult.
[4]
The underlying
structure of verb forms involving morphophonological processes is given in
footnotes. In this example, the underlying form of
w-oq’-ari
is
|w-eq’-ari|.
[5]
The underlying form of
w-oƛ-ari
is
|w-eƛ-ari|.
[6]
The only exceptions to
the semantic rule of class assignment are
ãde
‘person’ and
mik’e
‘child’, which in
the singular trigger N agreement, whereas the corresponding plural forms
ãdo
and
mik’eli
regularly trigger HPL
agreement.
[7]
It seems that in AR
Akhvakh, all noun dependents in canonical NPs optionally take class suffixes
agreeing with the head noun, but in the data I have collected in
Axaxdərə, noun dependents other than adjectives never occur with
agreement marks in canonical NPs, and suffixal agreement of adjectives never
occurs in classes other than HPL.
[8]
The underlying form of
gw-ēri
is
|gwi(j)-ari|.
[9]
In principle,
zero-marked genitive characterizes M and HPL NPs, whereas
-ƛ̱i
is used with F, N or
NPL NPs, but this rule is not very strict, and variations are
observed.
[10]
In AR Akhvakh
-u
has been identified as ablative proper,
and
-une
as perlative, but in AD Akhvakh,
these two endings are in free variation.
[11]
Words obligatorily
including a class marker are conventionally quoted in the non-human singular (N)
form, with the class marker between small angle brackets.
[12]
In Akhvakh,
non-verbal predications involving neither the copula nor the verb
‹b›ik’uruƛa
‘be’ are exceptional in statements. By contrast, the omission of the
copula regularly occurs in questions.
[13]
In AR Akhvakh,
attributive or predicative adjectives optionally show suffixal
inflection.
[14]
In this
enumeration, each suffix is given in the form of its default allomorph, i.e.,
the allomorph occurring in the absence of any morphophonological process
triggered by the stem.
[15]
There is no
specific form of the indirective past in the HPL class, and this gap is filled
by the HPL form of the perfect, an analytic tense consisting of the general
converb of the auxiliated verb and the copula in auxiliary
function.
[16]
For more detailed
presentation/discussion of speech act role distinctions in Akhvakh verb
morphology, see (Creissels 2008a), (Creissels2008b).
[17]
In addition to
variations due to morphophonological interaction with the stem, these suffixes
show (partly optional) variations involving class agreement :
-ari
takes the form
-iri
if the absolutive argument belongs to
the HPL class, but invariably appears as
-ari
in the other classes, whereas
-ada
obligatorily appears as
-idi
if the
absolutive argument belongs to the HPL class and undergoes optional class
agreement in the other classes, resulting in the variants M
-ada ~
-adawe ~
-ado
, F
-ada ~
-adaje ~
-ade
, N
-ada ~
-adabe ~
-ade
, NPL
-ada ~
-adare ~
-ade
.
[18]
Assertive agreement
has not been identified in previous studies of Akhvakh – (Magometbekova
1967), (Kibrik 1985). Magomedbekova (1967) describes an ‘optional’
1st vs. 2nd/3rd person contrast, but does not provide examples of interrogative
clauses that could reveal the existence of an assertor’s involvement
marking pattern. In the grammatical sketch included in the Akhvakh-Russian
dictionary, the two verbal endings expressing distinctions in assertive
agreement are just mentioned as two possible marks of the same tense
(prošedšee očevidnoe, i.e. ‘past of direct
knowledge’), without any indication about their distribution or difference
in meaning. However, the dictionary itself includes many examples suggesting a
pattern similar to that of
Axaxdərə
Akhvakh, and this was confirmed by the discussions I had with Indira Abdulaeva.
The only Caucasian language in which assertive agreement has been recognized so
far is the Mehweb dialect of Dargwa – (Magometov 1982). Similar patterns
(more commonly termed ‘conjunct/disjunct systems’) have been first
described for Tibetan, Newari, and a few other Tibeto-Burman languages –
(Hale 1980), (DeLancey 1986), (DeLancey 1990), (DeLancey 1992), (Hargreaves
2005), and have also been signaled in the Barbacoan languages spoken in Colombia
and Ecuador – (Dickinson 2000), (Curnow 2002a), (Curnow 2002b), and in the
Papuan language Oksapmin – (Loughnane 2007).
[19]
On the specialized
converbs of Akhvakh, see (Creissels To appear).
[20]
The underlying form
of
w-ašl-ēri
is
|w-ašla(j)-iri|.
[21]
The underlying form
of
m-ič-unuƛa
is
|b-ĩč-uruƛa|.
[22]
The underlying form
of
gw-īri
is
|gwi(j)-iri|.
[23]
The underlying form
of
r-eq̄-ōruƛa
is
|r-eq̄a(j)-uruƛa|.
[24]
The underlying form
of
c̱’-ēdaλ̱a
is
|c̱’a(b)-idaλ̱a|.
[25]
The underlying form
of
b-oč’il-āri
is
|b-oč’ila(j)-ari|.
[26]
The underlying form
of
m-ič-ala
is
|b-ĩč-ala|.
[27]
The underlying form
of
m-īda
is
|b-(ãʔ-)ida|.
[28]
The underlying form
of
gw-ēre
is
|gwi(j)-ere|.
[29]
On participial
constructions as a relative clause formation strategy, see in particular (Comrie
& Polinsky 1999).
[30]
Akhvakh also has a
correlative relative clause construction, but it is much less usual than the
participial construction.
[31]
For a historical
explanation of this situation, see (Creissels 2008a).
[32]
The underlying form
of
kw-ī̃da
is
|kwĩ(λ)-ida|.
[33]
The underlying form
of
m-ač-ika
is
|b-ãč-ika|.
[34]
The underlying form
of
w-ošq̄-iƛa
is
|w-ešq̄-iƛa |.
[35]
The underlying form
of
j-ā̃da
is
|j-(ãʔ-)ada|.
[36]
The underlying form
of
gw-ēda
is
|gwi(j)-ada|.
[37]
The underlying form
of
w-ī̃ƛa
is
|w-(ãʔ-)iƛa|.
[38]
The underlying form
of
w-oƛ-ari
is
|w-eƛ-ari|.
[39]
The underlying form
of
w-ux̱-uwi
is
|w-ix̱-uwi |.
|